Skip to main content

Neural Simulation and Social Cognition

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Mirror Neuron Systems

Part of the book series: Contemporary Neuroscience ((CNEURO))

Abstract

This article reviews the claim that mirror neurons are simulating neurons and the basis of an implicit simulation theory in regard to how we understand other persons. I claim that the equation of mirror system activation with an implicit simulation is unjustified, and I offer an alternative interpretation of the scientific data. The alternative considers mirror system activation as underlying part of an enactive perception in the social context.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Elsewhere, however, Iacoboni does invoke mindreading: “Mirror neurons suggest that we pretend to be in another person's mental shoes. In fact, with mirror neurons we do not have to pretend, we practically are in another person's mind. … You either simulate with mirror neurons, or the mental states of others are completely precluded to you” (quoted in Than 2005).

  2. 2.

    See Gallagher (2007) for this and other objections to explicit ST.

  3. 3.

    The requirement that the simulation has to be concretely similar also raises problems for the instrumental and pretense conditions even for the explicit version of ST. If our simulation has to be concretely similar to the simulated state for it to be considered a simulation, assuming explicit instrumental control of our simulation process, how will we know how to run or control our simulation unless we already know in some detail what the other’s state is like. And how do we come by that knowledge? If the answer is through simulation, then we have an infinite regress. In regard to explicit pretense, Fisher (2006), who models simulation as a reasoning process, rejects this aspect as inconsistent with simulation being concretely similar, for if we simulate a reasoning process, we are really reasoning, and not just pretending to.

  4. 4.

    Csibra concludes: “With strongly unequal distribution of types of action or types of grip, one could find a relatively high proportion of good match between the [observed action vs executed action] domains even if there were no causal relation between them. Without such a statistical analysis, it remains uncertain whether the cells that satisfy the definition of ‘mirror neurons' (i.e., the ones that discharge both with execution and observation of actions) do indeed have 'mirror properties' in the everyday use of this term (i.e., are generally activated by the same action in both domains)” (2005, 3).

  5. 5.

    In the phenomenological tradition, this idea of kinaesthetic coordination was expressed by Husserl as early as 1908 (see Husserl 1973). See Berthoz and Petit (2006).

References

  • Adams, F. (2001). Empathy, neural imaging, and the theory versus simulation debate. Mind and Language, 16 (4): 368–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allison, T., Puce, Q., and McCarthy, G. (2000). Social perception from visual cues: role of the STS region. Trends in Cognitive Science, 4 (7): 267–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Avenanti, A., & Aglioti S. M. (2006). The sensorimotor side of empathy for pain. In M. Mancia (ed.), Psychoanalysis and neuroscience (pp. 235–256). Milan: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Baird, J. A. & Baldwin, D. A. (2001). Making sense of human behavior: Action parsing and intentional inference. In B. F. Malle, L. J. Moses, & D. A. Baldwin (Eds.). Intentions and intentionality: Foundations of social cognition (pp. 193–206). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, D. A. (1993). Infants' ability to consult the speaker for clues to word reference. Journal of Child Language, 20, 395–418.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin, D. A. & Baird, J. A. (2001). Discerning intentions in dynamic human action. Trends in Cognitive Science, 5 (4), 171–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J. L. (1996). The moral significance of birth. Ethics, 106, 378–403.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bernier, P. (2002). From simulation to theory. In J. Dokic & J. Proust (eds.), Simulation and knowledge of action (pp. 33–48). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertenthal, B. I., Proffitt, D. R. & Cutting, J. E. (1984). Infant sensitivity to figural coherence in biomechanical motions. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 37, 213–30.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Berthoz, A. & Petit, J-L. (2006). Phénoménologie et physiologie de l’action. Paris: Odile Jacob.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blakeslee, S. (2006). Cells that read minds. New York Times, January 10, 2006. http://www.nytimes.com/2006/01/10/science/10mirr.html. Accessed January 2006; May 2007.

  • Csibra, G. (2005). Mirror neurons and action observation. Is simulation involved? ESF Interdisciplines. http://www.interdisciplines.org/mirror/papers/.

  • Currie, G. & Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • deVignemont, F. (2004). The co-consciousness hypothesis. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 3(1): 97–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Decety, J. & Grèzes, J. (2006). The power of simulation: Imagining one's own and other's behavior. Brain Research, 1079, 4–14.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Dokic, J. & Proust, J. (2002). Introduction. In J. Dokic and J. Proust (Eds.), Simulation and knowledge of action (pp. vii–xxi). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, J. C. (2006). Does simulation theory really involve simulation? Philosophical Psychology, 19 (4), 417–432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fogassi, L., Ferrari, P.F., Gesierich, B., Rozzi, S., Chersi, F. & Rizzolatti, G., (2005). Parietal lobe: From action organization to intention understanding. Science, 308, 662–667.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Fogassi, L. & Gallese, V. (2002). The neural correlates of action understanding in non-human primates. In M. I. Stamenov & V. Gallese (Eds.), Mirror Neurons and the Evolution of Brain and Language (pp. 13–35). Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (1996). The moral significance of primitive self-consciousness. Ethics, 107, 129–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2001). The practice of mind: Theory, simulation, or interaction? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8 (5–7), 83–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2007). Simulation trouble. Social Neuroscience, 2 (3–4), 353–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. & Hutto, D. (2008). Primary interaction and narrative practice. In: Zlatev, Racine, Sinha & Itkonen (Eds.). The Shared Mind: Perspectives on Intersubjectivity (pp.17–38). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. & Meltzoff, A. (1996). The earliest sense of self and others: Merleau-Ponty and recent developmental studies. Philosophical Psychology, 9: 213–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2007). Before and below ‘theory of mind': embodied simulation and the neural correlates of social cognition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B-Biological Sciences, 362 (1480), 659–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2005). ‘Being like me': Self-other identity, mirror neurons and empathy, In Hurley, S. & Chater, N. (eds.), Perspectives on Imitation I (pp. 101–118). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V. (2001). The ‘shared manifold’ hypothesis: from mirror neurons to empathy’. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8, 33–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., Eagle, M.N. & Migone, P. (2007). Intentional attunement: Mirror neurons and the neural underpinnings of interpersonal relations. Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association, 55 (1), 131–176.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2002). Simulation theory and mental concepts. In J. Dokic & J. Proust (Eds.), Simulation and knowledge of action (pp. 1–19). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2005a). Mirror Systems, Social Understanding and Social Cognition. Interdisciplines. (http://www.interdisciplines.org/mirror/papers/3).

  • Goldman, A. (2005b). Imitation, mind reading, and simulation. In Hurley and Chater (Eds.) Perspectives on Imitation II (pp. 79–93). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. Sripada, C. S. (2005). Simulationist models of face-based emotion recognition. Cognition, 94 (2005), 193–213.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. & Meltzoff, A. (1997). Words, Thoughts, and Theories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, R. M. (2004). Folk psychology as mental simulation. In N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. (http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2004/entries/folkpsych-simulation/).

  • Gordon, R. M. (2005). Intentional agents like myself. In S. Hurley & N. Chater (eds.), Perspectives on Imitation I (pp. 95–106). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grèzes, J. & Decety, J. (2001). Functional anatomy of execution, mental simulation, and verb generation of actions: A meta-analysis. Human Brain Mapping 12, 1–19.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. L. (2005). Active perception and perceiving action: The shared circuits model. In T. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. L. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973). Ding und Raum. Husserliana 16. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Iacoboni, M., Molnar-Szakacs, I., Gallese, V., Buccino, G., Mazziotta, J. & Rizzolatti, G. (2005). Grasping the intentions of others with one's own mirror neuron system. PLoS Biology, 3 (79), 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (2003). The mechanism of self-recognition in humans. Behavioural Brain Research, 142: 1–15

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (2001) Neural simulation of action: A unifying mechanism for motor cognition. Neuroimage, 14, 103–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. & Pacherie, E. (2004). Agency, simulation, and self-identification. Mind and Language, 19 (2): 113–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, S. C. (2000). The recognition of mentalistic agents in infancy. Trends in Cognitive Science, 4: 22–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, S. et al. (1998). Whose gaze will infants follow? The elicitation of gaze-following in 12-month-old infants. Developmental Science, 1: 233–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, J. T. & Iacoboni, M. (2006). Getting a grip on other minds: Mirror neurons, intention understanding, and cognitive empathy. Social neuroscience. 1 (3–4): 175–83.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Legerstee, M. (1991). The role of person and object in eliciting early imitation. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 51: 423–33.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N. & Brooks, R. (2001). 'Like Me' as a building block for understanding other minds: Bodily acts, attention, and intention. In B. F. Malle, et al. (eds.), Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of Social Cognition (pp. 171–191). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The Visible and the Invisible. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minio-Paluello I, Avenanti A, and Aglioti, S. M. (2006). Social Neuroscience 1 (3–4): 320–333.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Molnar-Szakacs I., Kaplan J., Greenfield PM, Iacoboni M. (2006). Observing complex action sequences: The role of the fronto-parietal mirror neuron system. Neuroimage 33 (3): 923–935.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, D. G., Hobson, R. P. & Lee, A. (1997). Components of person perception: An investigation with autistic, non-autistic retarded and typically developing children and adolescents. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 15: 401–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morton, A. (1996). Folk psychology is not a predictive device. Mind 105: 119–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman-Norlund, RD. Noordzij, ML. Meulenbroek, RGJ, Bekkering, H. (2007). Exploring the brain basis of joint attention: Co-ordination of actions, goals and intentions. Social Neuroscience 2 (1): 48–65.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oberman, L. M. & Ramachandran, V. S. (2007). The Simulating Social Mind: The Role of the Mirror Neuron System and Simulation in the Social and Communicative Deficits of Autism Spectrum Disorders. Psychological Bulletin 133 (2): 310–327.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, W., Baron-Cohen, S. & Rutter, M. (1992). The role of eye-contact in the detection of goals: Evidence from normal toddlers, and children with autism or mental handicap. Development and Psychopathology, 4: 375–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M.J. (2006). Rethinking Commonsense Psychology: A Critique of Folk Psychology, Theory of Mind and Simulation. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Fogassi, L. & Gallese V. (2000). Cortical mechanisms subserving object grasping and action recognition: A new view on the cortical motor functions. In M. S. Gazzaniga (ed.), The New Cognitive Neurosciences (pp. 539–52). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., Gallese V. & Fogassi, L. (1996). Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor actions. Cognitive Brain Research, 3: 131–141.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Ruby, P., Decety, J., (2001). Effect of subjective perspective taking during simulation of action: a PET investigation of agency. Nature Neuroscience 4, 546–550.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Senju, A, Johnson MH and Csibra G. (2006). The development and neural basis of referential gaze perception. Social Neuroscience 1 (3–4): 220–234.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, B. J. & Tremoulet, P. D. (2000). Perceptual causality and animacy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4 (8): 299–309.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Than, K. (2005). Scientists Say Everyone Can Read Minds. LiveScience 27 April 2005 (http://www.livescience.com/humanbiology/050427_mind_readers.html)

  • Trevarthen, C. (1980). The foundations of intersubjectivity: Development of interpersonal and cooperative understanding of infants. In D.R. Olson (ed.), The Social Foundation of Language and Thought: Essays in Honor of Jerome S. Bruner (316–341). New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. (1979). Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary intersubjectivity. In M. Bullowa (ed.), Before Speech. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. & Hubley, P. (1978). Secondary intersubjectivity: Confidence, confiding and acts of meaning in the first year. In A. Lock (ed.), Action, gesture and symbol:The emergence of language. San Diego,CA: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Urgesi, C. Candidi, M. Ionta, S., & Aglioti, S.M. (2007). Representation of body identity and body actions in extrastriate body area and ventral premotor cortex. Nature Neuroscience 10 (1): 30–31.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Uddin, LQ, Kaplan JT, Molnar-Szakacs I, Zaidel E, and Iacoboni, M. (2005). Self-face recognition activates a frontoparietal “mirror” network in the right hemisphere: an event-related fMRI study. Neuroimage 25 (3): 926–935.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E. & Rosch, E. (1991). The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, A. S. (1982). Intermodal perception of expressive behaviors by human infants. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 33, 514–35.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Shaun Gallagher .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2008 Humana Press, a part of Springer Science+Business Media, LLC

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gallagher, S. (2008). Neural Simulation and Social Cognition. In: Pineda, J.A. (eds) Mirror Neuron Systems. Contemporary Neuroscience. Humana Press. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-59745-479-7_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics