Skip to main content

Frozen Embryos and Frozen Concepts

  • Chapter
Book cover Bioethics and the Fetus

Part of the book series: Biomedical Ethics Reviews ((BER))

  • 75 Accesses

Abstract

The case of Davis v. Davis made headlines around the world. The facts were simple. Mr. and Mrs. Davis had been unable to conceive, and Mrs. Davis had undertaken “in vitro procedures,” as the court put it, to attempt to produce a child.1 Eggs were taken from her and inseminated with sperm from Mr. Davis, and, of the resulting fertilized eggs, two were implanted immediately without effect and seven frozen for later implantation. The couple, meanwhile, decided to divorce, and the issue between them of importance for the court concerned the disposition of the seven frozen embryos.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes and References

  1. References to the case are to Junior L. Davis v. Mary Sue Davis v. Ray King, M.D., d/b/a. Fertility Center of East Tennessee, In the Circuit Court for Blount County, Tennessee, at Maryville, Equity Division (Division I), 9–21–89.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Davis v. Davis, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Davis v. Davis, 20.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Davis v. Davis, 17.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Davis v. Davis, 6.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Davis v. Davis, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Davis v. Davis, 15.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Davis v. Davis, 17.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Davis v. Davis, A7.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Davis v. Davis, Cl.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Davis v. Davis, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Davis v. Davis, 16.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Davis v. Davis, 15.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Davis v. Davis, 17.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Davis v. Davis, 6,20.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Davis v. Davis, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Davis v. Davis, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Davis v. Davis, 20.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Davis v. Davis, 20.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Davis v. Davis, A6.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Davis v. Davis, 12.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Davis v. Davis, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Davis v. Davis, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Davis v. Davis, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Davis v. Davis, 15.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Davis v. Davis, 13.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Davis v. Davis, 17.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Davis v. Davis, 15–16.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Davis v. Davis, 15.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Davis v. Davis, 19,20.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Davis v. Davis, 20.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Davis v. Davis, 15.

    Google Scholar 

  33. John Stuart Mill (1957) Utilitarianism Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  35. For the most thorough discussion of this case, see Don E. Fehrenbacher (1978) The Dred Scott Case: Its Significance in American Law and Politics Oxford University Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  36. The Court left open the possibility that Congress might grant citizenship to aliens who were black. Since Congress had not done so, any black living within the United States would not be a citizen.

    Google Scholar 

  37. It is an often ignored feature of Rawls’ presentation of his theory of justice that he assumes that the conditions of society in which the contractors will find themselves are improved enough that it is “irrational from the standpoint of the original position to acknowledge a lesser liberty for the sake of greater material gains and amenities of office” (John Rawls (1971) A Theory of Justice Harvard University Press, Cambridge, p. 542; also see e.g., pp. 151–52). He lifts the veil of ignorance enough, that is, that those contracting know that, however they end up, they will not be willing to trade liberty for any other goods. So, instead of choosing the general theory of justice, in which the goods are not ranked, the contractors choose the two principles of justice, in which they are.

    Google Scholar 

  38. See Rawls, op. cit., especially pp. 505 and 145.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Consider how Rawls must treat the rest of the moral universe. He claims that his contractarian view can be extended to all moral creation, not just to those beings entitled to justice, but those beings who are not entitled to enter into the original position will have their moral status determined by those self-interested beings, disinterested in the interests of others, who do enter the original position. Any other beings have no standing within contract theory unless they are subject to whatever moral principles are chosen from the original position, and, in contract theory, that means they must choose the principles, i.e., must be in the original position. So, to be a moral being entitled to claim justice is to be within the original position. For a more detailed discussion of this issue, see Michael S. Pritchard and Wade L. Robison (1981) Justice and the treatment of animals: A critique of Rawls. Environmental Ethics 3, 55–61.

    Google Scholar 

  40. To make my general point, I can ignore such complications of detail as how pleasure is related to happiness and whether Mill is committed to providing the greatest happiness or the greatest pleasure.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Rawls says that moral persons have two characteristics, the capacity for a sense of justice (which implies a capacity to keep one’ s commitments) and the capacity to have a conception of their good (op. cit., p. 505). I may seem to ignore the latter, but, in fact, I think it is also a contractual condition for Rawls. It is the capacity for a conception of their good that makes moral beings capable of being bargaining agents. So, the capacity for a sense of justice allows moral persons to keep their contracts once they are made, and the capacity for a conception of their good makes moral persons willing to contract to begin with. I have ignored whatever complications this addition would make for the chapter because I do not think it will change the basic claims.

    Google Scholar 

  42. The procedure of contract theories provides, then, a general analytic method for the comparative study of conceptions of justice. One tries to set out the different conditions embodied in the contractual situation in which their principles would be chosen“ (Rawls, op. cit., pp. 121–122).

    Google Scholar 

  43. In the Preface to the Foundations, Kant distinguishes between various kinds of knowledge, arguing that though there is what he calls practical anthropology, the empirical part of ethics, the proper job of philosophy is to concern itself with constructing “a pure moral philosophy which is completely freed from everything which may be only empirical and thus belong to anthropology” ([1985] Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals [Louis White Beck, ed.], Macmillan Publishing Company, New York, p. 5). He goes on to say that “philosophy which mixes pure principles with empirical ones does not deserve the name,…Muchless…the name of moral philosophy…” (Ibid., p. 6). I read this as claiming that a utilitarian theory, which bases its principles on a natural feature of human beings, is not really philosophy at all—the philosopher’s ultimate rejection of a competing theory.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Op. cit., p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  45. I heard a news report that she does not want them implanted now, but I have been unable to verify the report.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1991 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Robison, W.L. (1991). Frozen Embryos and Frozen Concepts. In: Humber, J.M., Almeder, R.F. (eds) Bioethics and the Fetus. Biomedical Ethics Reviews. Humana Press, Totowa, NJ. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-59259-445-0_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-59259-445-0_4

  • Publisher Name: Humana Press, Totowa, NJ

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4757-4609-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-59259-445-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics