Skip to main content

Abstract

A recurrent theme in developmental theory has been that the process of development is intrinsically open-ended (e.g., Lerner, 1986, p.178f). The notion that development never ends has led to the kind of life-span psychology that is currently popular. Formerly, psychologists often felt differently. They sometimes talked as if one’s character is crystallized early on in life, and has a fixed structure against which one may later have to struggle. Freud (1966) is often cited in this connection. Another example is James’ (1890) famous discussion of habit.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Benjafield, J. (1985). A review of recent research on the Golden Section. Empirical Studies of the Arts, 3, 117–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benjafield, J. (1987). An historical, social analysis of imagery and concreteness. British Journal of Social Psychology, 26, 155–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benjafield, X., & Muckenheim, R. (1989). A further historicodevelopmental study of the interpersonal circle. Canadian Journal of Behavioural Science, 21, 83–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, G. S. (1969). The Laws of Form. London: Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, J. M. (1981). The life and death of Simone Weil. In G. A. White (Ed.), Simone Weil: Interpretation of a life. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coles, R. (1982). Simone Weil’s Mind. In G. A. White (Ed.), Simone Weil: Interpretation of a life. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drury, M. (1973). The Danger of Words. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1966). Some thoughts on development and regression—aetiology. New introductory lectures on psychoanalysis (pp. 339–357). New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological theory and women’s development. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, D. Godel, Escher, Bach: An eternal golden braid. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, P., & Brecht, G. (1975). Vicious circles and infinity. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W (1890). The principles of psychology. New York: Holt.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lerner, R. M. (1986). Concepts and theories of human development. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, (1961). Minds, machines and Godel. Philosophy, 36, 112.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGuinness, B. (1966). The mysticism of the Tractates. Philosophical Review, 75, 305–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchison, G. J. (1977). Phyllotaxis and the Fibonacci series. Science, 196, 270–275.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1957). Logic and psychology. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget, J. (1970). Structuralism. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1974). Introduction. In L. Wittgenstein (Ed.), Tractatus logico-philosophicus. New York: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stevens, P. S. (1974). Patterns in nature. Boston: Houghton-Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, D. W (1929). Excess and defect. Mind, 38, 43–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weil, S. (1968). On science necessity and the love of God. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weil, S. (1971). The need for roots. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weil, S. (1977). Metaxu. In G. Panichas (Ed.), A Simone Weil reader. New York: McKay.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wisdom, J. (1957). Philosophy and psychoanalysis. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1956). Remarks on the foundations of mathematics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1969). Notebooks 1914–1916. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. (Original work published in 1922)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1991 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Benjafield, J. (1991). The End of Development. In: Leenaars, A.A. (eds) Life Span Perspectives of Suicide. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-0724-0_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4899-0724-0_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Boston, MA

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4899-0726-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4899-0724-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics