Skip to main content

Omnipotence: Moving and Staying Power

  • Chapter
Superior Beings
  • 75 Accesses

Abstract

The resolution of the first paradox of omniscience in Chapter 4, via the theory of moves, was thoroughly secular. It generally favored the stronger or quicker player, in a particular sense, and thus could be viewed as unfair to the other player, though he always obtained at least his security level in a game.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Martin Gardner rejects the view that there are limitations: “Let me confess at once that I find something profoundly impious, almost blasphemous, about setting limits of any sort on the power of God to bring things about in any manner that He chooses.” Martin Gardner, The Ambidextrous Universe: Mirror Asymmetry and Time-Reversed Worlds, 2nd ed. rev. (New York: Scribner’s, 1979), p. 125.

    Google Scholar 

  2. For recent investigations into such questions in the philosophy of religion, see The Power of God: Readings on Omnipotence and Evil, ed. Linwood Urban and Douglas N. Walton (New York: Oxford University Press, 1978); Anthony Kenny, The God of the Philosophers (Oxford: Clarendon, 1979);

    Google Scholar 

  3. Gary Rosenkrantz and Joshua Hoffman, What an omnipotent agent can do, Int. J. Philos. Religion 11, 1 (Spring 1980), 1–19;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. W. S. Anglin, Can God create a being He cannot control? Analysis 40, 4 (October 1980), 220–223;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. and Edward Wierenger, Omnipotence defined, Philos, and Phenomenological Res. 43 (1982) (forthcoming). None of this literature analyzes the relationship between a superior and ordinary being as a game, which in my view puts the question of omnipotence, as well as omniscience, in a fundamentally new framework. Omnipotence, by the way, seems to have confounded philosophers more than omniscience, perhaps because “the notion of infinite power has seemed too obscure, too shrouded in mystery and ineffability for us to analyze our feelings of awe and bring them into the domain of pure concepts.” The Power of God, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Material in this and the next section is based largely on Steven J. Brams, Omniscience and omnipotence: how they may help—or hurt—in a game, Inquiry 25, 2 (June 1982), 217–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Steven J. Brams and Marek P. Hessel, Absorbing outcomes in 2 × 2 games, Behavioral Sci. 27, 2 (October 1982), 393–401.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  8. Leszek Kolakowski, Religion (New York: Oxford University Press, 1982), p. 140.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Material in this and the next two sections is based largely on Steven J. Brams and Marek P. Hessel, Staying power in sequential games, Theory and Decision (forthcoming); see also D. Marc Kilgour, Equilibria for far-sighted players, Theory and Decision (forthcoming), who extends the notion of nonmyopic equilibrium (see citation in note 7) to most games in which S-power is not effective.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Steven J. Brams and Donald Wittman, Nonmyopic equilibria in 2 × 2 games, Conflict Management and Peace Sci. 6, 1 (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  11. This is in fact true of S-power outcomes in all two-person finite games, as shown in Brams and Hessel, Staying power in sequential games.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Saint Aurelius Augustinus, The Confessions of Saint Augustine, translated by Edward B. Pusey (New York: Modern Library, 1949).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Karl Barth, Church Dogmatics, translated by G. W. Bromily (New York: Harper & Row, 1962); see also Hans Küng, Justification: The Doctrine of Karl Barth and a Catholic Reflection (Philadelphia: Westminister, 1981).

    Google Scholar 

  14. It would also imply a kind of “metaphysical determinism,” which Karl R. Popper rejects in The Open Universe: An Argument for Indeterminism, ed. W. W. Bartley III (Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, 1982), pp 87–92.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1983 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Brams, S.J. (1983). Omnipotence: Moving and Staying Power. In: Superior Beings. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4757-1807-2_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4757-1807-2_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, New York, NY

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4757-1809-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4757-1807-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics