Skip to main content

Symbolic, Conceptual and Subconceptual Representations

  • Chapter

Abstract

Cognitive science aims at understanding how information is represented and processed in different kinds of agents, biological as well as artificial. The research has two overarching goals. One is explanatory: by studying the cognitive activities of humans and other animals, one formulates theories of different kinds of cognition. The theories are tested either by experiments or by computer simulations. The other goal is constructive: by building artefacts like chess-playing programs, robots, animates, etc., one attempts to construct systems that can solve various cognitive tasks. For both kinds of goals, a key problem is how the information used by the cognitive system is to be modelled in an appropriate way.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. A. Newell and H. Simon, Computer science as empirical inquiry: symbols and search, CACM 19:113–116 (1976).

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  2. J.A. Fodor, Representations, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1981).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Z. Pylyshyn, Computation and Cognition, Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1984).

    Google Scholar 

  4. J.A. Fodor and Z. Pylyshyn, Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis, Cognition 28:3–71 (1988).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. S.E. Palmer, Fundamental aspects of cognitive representation, in: Cognition and Categorization, E. Rosch and B. B. Lloyd eds., Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale, NJ, 259–303 (1978).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Z. Pylyshyn, Computation and Cognition, Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1984). Quotation from p. 29: “ … to be in a certain representational state is to have a certain symbolic expression in some part of memory.”

    Google Scholar 

  7. Z. Pylyshyn, Computation and Cognition, Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1984). Quotation from p. 194.

    Google Scholar 

  8. J.A. Fodor, Representations, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1981). Quotation from p. 230.

    Google Scholar 

  9. J. McCarthy and P. Hayes, Some philosophical problems from the standpoint of artificial intelligence, in: Machine Intelligence, Vol. 4, B. Meltzer and D. Michie eds., Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh (1969).

    Google Scholar 

  10. L.-E. Janlert, Modeling change — the frame problem, in: The robot’s dilemma: the frame problem in artificial intelligence, Z. Pylyshyn ed., Ablex, Norwood, NJ (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  11. J. Stewart, Cognition = life: implications for higher-level cognition, Behav. Proc. 35:311–326 (1996). Quotation from p. 317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. J.A. Fodor, Representations, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1981). Quotation from p. 231.

    Google Scholar 

  13. J.A. Fodor, Representations, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1981). Quotation from p. 203.

    Google Scholar 

  14. S. Harnad, The symbol grounding problem, Physica D 42:335–346 (1990).

    Google Scholar 

  15. J. Stewart, Cognition = life: implications for higher-level cognition, Behav. Proc. 35:311–326 (1996). Quotation from p 323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. CG. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation, and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, Free Press, New York, NY (1965).

    Google Scholar 

  17. N. Goodman, Fact, Fiction, and Forecast, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1955).

    Google Scholar 

  18. D.E. Rumelhart and J.L. McClelland, Parallel Distributed Processing, Vols. 1 & 2, Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1986).

    Google Scholar 

  19. S.E. Palmer, Fundamental aspects of cognitive representation, in: Cognition and Categorization, E. Rosch and B. B. Lloyd eds., Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Hillsdale, NJ (1978), pp. 270–272.

    Google Scholar 

  20. T. Kohonen, Self-Organization and Associative Memory, 2nd Edition, Springer-Verlag, Berlin (1988).

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. H.R. Schiffman, Sensation and Perception, 2nd ed., John Wiley and Sons, New York, NY (1982).

    Google Scholar 

  22. P. Gärdenfors, Induction, conceptual spaces and AI, Philosophy of Science 57:78–95 (1990).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  23. P. Gärdenfors, Frameworks for properties: Possible worlds vs. conceptual spaces, in: Language, Knowledge, and Intentionality, L. Haaparanta, M. Kusch, and I. Niiniluoto eds., Helsinki (Acta Philosophica Fennica. 49:383–407) (1990).

    Google Scholar 

  24. P. Gärdenfors, Three levels of inductive inference, in: Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science IX, D. Prawitz, B. Skyrms and D. Westerståhl eds., Elsevier Science, Amsterdam, 427–449 (1994).

    Google Scholar 

  25. A. Gabrielsson, Music psychology — A survey of problems and current research activities, in: Basic Musical Functions and Musical Ability, Publications issued by the Royal Swedish Academy of Music, 32:7–80 (1981).

    Google Scholar 

  26. P. Gärdenfors, Semantics, conceptual spaces and the dimensions of music, in: Essays on the Philosophy of Music, V. Rantala, L. Rowell, and E. Tarasti eds., Helsinki (Acta Philosophica Fennica, vol. 43:9–27) (1988).

    Google Scholar 

  27. H.R. Schiffman, Sensation and Perception, 2nd ed., John Wiley and Sons, New York, NY (1982). Quotation from p. 138.

    Google Scholar 

  28. G. Lakoff, Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  29. R. W. Langacker, Foundations of Cognitive Grammar, Vol. 1, Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  30. P. Gärdenfors, Induction, conceptual spaces and AI, Philosophy of Science 57:78–95 (1990).

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  31. W.V.O. Quine, Natural kinds, in: Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, Columbia University Press, New York, NY, 114–138 (1969).

    Google Scholar 

  32. W.V.O. Quine, Natural kinds, in: Ontological Relativity and Other Essays, Columbia University Press, New York, NY, 114–138 (1969). Quotation from p.117.

    Google Scholar 

  33. For a discussion of the role of conceptual spaces in science, see P. Gärdenfors, Induction, conceptual spaces and AI, Philosophy of Science 57:78–95 (1990), and P. Gärdenfors, Induction and the evolution of conceptual spaces, in: Charles Peirce and the Philosophy of Science, E. C. Moore ed., University of Alabama Press, Tuscaloosa, 72-88 (1993).

    Google Scholar 

  34. A. Karmiloff-Smith, Beyond Modularity: A Developmental Perspective on Cognitive Science, Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1992). She points out that the fact that the brain organizes information in a domain-specific way does not entail that the brain is modular as has been argued by J. Fodor.

    Google Scholar 

  35. D. Kirsch, Today the earwig, tomorrow man?, Artificial Intelligence 47:161–184 (1991). Quotation from p. 163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. P. M. Churchland, Some reductive strategies in cognitive neurobiology, Mind 95, 379:279–309 (1986).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. J. Foss, The percept and vector function theories of the brain, Philosophy of Science 55:511–537 (1988).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Neurophysiological processes are often described in this way too. For example, C.R. Gallistel, The Organization of Learning, Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1990) writes on p. 519: “At the retina, the infinitely dimensional spectral vector is collapsed into a three-dimensional representation by the cones. The cone representation of spectra, while it grossly reduces the dimensionality of the stimulus, at least preserves the unipolarity of light. This unipolarity is lost, however, in the coordinate transformation that occurs between the cones and VI. By the time color signals appear in VI, they are bipolar variables.”

    Google Scholar 

  39. P. Smolensky, On the proper treatment of connectionism, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11:1–23 (1988). Quotation from p. 23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. P.S. Churchland, Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind/Brain. Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1986). Quotation from pp. 281–283.

    Google Scholar 

  41. In P.S. Churchland, Neurophilosophy: Toward a Unified Science of the Mind/Brain. Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1986), we find the following general idea: “… the brain represents various aspects of reality by a position in a suitable state space; and the brain performs computations on such representations by means of general coordinate transformations from one state space to another.”

    Google Scholar 

  42. B.E. Stein and M.A. Meredith, The Merging of the Senses, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. (1993). Quotation from p. 83.

    Google Scholar 

  43. C.R. Gallistel, The Organization of Learning, Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1990). Quotation from p. 477.

    Google Scholar 

  44. J.R. Anderson, The Architecture of Cognition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1983).

    Google Scholar 

  45. A. Newell, Unified Theories of Cognition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (1990).

    Google Scholar 

  46. T. van Gelder, What might cognition be, if not computation?, Journal of Philosophy 92:345–381 (1995).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. P. Smolensky, On the proper treatment of connectionism, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11:1–23 (1988).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. P. Smolensky, Connectionism, constituency and the language of thought, in: Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics, B. Loewer and G. Rey eds., Blackwell’s, Oxford (1991). Quotation from p. 202–203.Also see P. Smolensky, On the proper treatment of connectionism, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11:1-23 (1988), hypothesis 8 on p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  49. C.R. Gallistel, The Organization of Learning, Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1990). Quotation from p. 476.

    Google Scholar 

  50. P.S. Churchland and J. Sejnowski, The Computational Brain, Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1992). Quotation from p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  51. P. M. Churchland, A Neurocomputational Perspective, Bradford Books, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1989). Quotation from p. 171.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1997 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gärdenfors, P. (1997). Symbolic, Conceptual and Subconceptual Representations. In: Cantoni, V., Di Gesù, V., Setti, A., Tegolo, D. (eds) Human and Machine Perception. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4615-5965-8_18

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4615-5965-8_18

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Boston, MA

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4613-7734-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-4615-5965-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics