The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of Choice

  • Amos Tversky
  • Daniel Kahneman

Abstract

Explanations and predictions of people’s choices, in everyday life as well as in the social sciences, are often founded on the assumption of human rationality. The definition of rationality has been much debated, but there is general agreement that rational choices should satisfy some elementary requirements of consistency and coherence. In this chapter, we describe decision problems in which people systematically violate the requirements of consistency and coherence, and we trace these violations to the psychological principles that govern the perception of decision problems and the evaluation of options.

Keywords

Rational Choice Prospect Theory Expect Utility Theory Reference Outcome Decision Weight 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Ainslie, G. (1975). Specious reward: A behavioral theory of impulsiveness and impulse control. Psychological Bulletin, 82, 463–496.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de Thomme devant le risque: Critique des postulats et axiomes de Tecole americaine. Econometrica, 21, 504–546.Google Scholar
  3. Einhorn, H. J., & Hogarth, R. M. (1981). Behavioral decision theory: Processes of judgment and choice. Annual Review of Psychology, 32, 53–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity, and the savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, 643–669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Elster, J. (1979). Ulysses and the sirens: Studies in rationality and irrationality. London: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Eraker, S. A., & Sox, H. C., (1981). Assessment of patients’ preferences for therapeutic outcomes. Medical Decision Making, 1, 29–39.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Fellner, W. (1965). Probability and profit: A study of economic behavior along Bayesian lines. Home-wood, IL: Irwin.Google Scholar
  8. Fischhoff, B., Slovic, P., & Lichtenstein S. (1980). Knowing what you want: Measuring labile values. In T. Wallsten (Ed.), Cognitive processes in choice and decision behavior. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  9. Fishburn, P. C. (1970). Utility theory for decision making. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
  10. Fishburn, P. C. & Kochenberger, G. A. (1979). Two-piece von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions. Decision Sciences, 10, 503–518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Galanter, E., & Pliner, P. (1974). Cross-modality matching of money against other continua. In H. R. Moskowitz & B. Scharf (Eds.), Sensation and Measurement. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  12. Grether, D. M. (1980). Bayes rule as a descriptive model: The representativeness heuristic. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 95, 537–557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Grether, D. M., & Plott, C. R. (1979.) Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon. American Economic Review, 69, 623–638.Google Scholar
  14. Hershey, J. C. & Schoemaker, P. J. H. (1980). Risk taking and problem context in the domain of losses: An expected-utility analysis. Journal of Risk and Insurance, 47, 111–132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47, 263–291.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Kunreuther, H. (1978). Disaster insurance protection: Public policy lessons. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
  17. Laughhunn, D. J., & Payne, J. W., & Crum, R. (1980). Managerial risk preferences for below-target returns. Management Science, 26, 1238–1249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Lichtenstein, S., & Slovic, P. (1971). Reversals of preference between bids and choices in gambling decisions. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 98, 46–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Lichtenstein, S., & Slovic, P. (1973). Response-induced reversals of preference in gambling: An extended replication in Las Vegas. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 101, 16–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Lieblich, I., & Lieblich, A. (1969). Effects of different payoff matrices on arithmetical estimation tasks: An attempt to produce rationality. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 29, 467–473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. MacCrimmon, K. R., & Larsson, S. (1979). Utility theory: Axioms versus paradoxes. In M. Allais & O. Hagen (Eds), Expected-utility hypotheses and the Allais paradox (Vol. 21.) Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  22. March, J. G. (1978). Bounded rationality, ambiguity, and the engineering of choice. Bell Journal of Economics, 9, 587–608.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. McGlothlin, W. H. (1956). Stability of choices among uncertain alternatives. American Journal of Psychology, 69, 604–615.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Nisbett, R. E., & Ross, L. (1980). Human inference: Strategies and shortcomings of social judgment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  25. Payne, J. W., & Braunstein, M. L. (1971). Preferences among gambles with equal underlying distributions. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 87, 13–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Payne, J. W., & Laughhunn, D. J., & Crum, R. (1980). Translation of gambles and aspiration-level effects in risky choice behavior. Management Science, 26, 1039–1060.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Pratt, J. W., & Wise, D., & Zeckhauser, R. (1979). Price differences in almost competitive markets. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 93, 189–211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Raiffa, H. (1968). Decision analysis: Introductory lectures on choices under uncertainty. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
  29. Savage, L. J. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
  30. Simon, H. A. (1955). A behavioral model of rational choice. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 69, 99–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Simon, H. A. (1956). Rational choice and the structure of the environment. Psychological Review, 63, 129–138.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Slovic, P., & Lichtenstein, S. (1968). Importance of variance preferences in gambling and decisions. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 78, 646–654.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (1974). Who accepts Savage’s axiom? Behavioral Science, 14, 368–373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Slovic, P., & Fischhoff, B., & Lichtenstein, S. (1977). Behavioral decision theory. Annual Review of Psychology, 28, 1–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Strotz, R., (1955–1956). Myopia and inconsistency in dynamic utility maximization. Review of Economic Studies, 23, 165–180.Google Scholar
  36. Thaler, R. (1980). Toward a positive theory of consumer choice. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 1, 39–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Thaler, R., & Shifrin, H. M. (1981). An economic theory of self-control. Journal of Political Economy, 89, 392–406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science, 185, 1124–1131.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1947). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Plenum Press, New York 1985

Authors and Affiliations

  • Amos Tversky
    • 1
  • Daniel Kahneman
    • 2
  1. 1.Department of PsychologyStanford UniversityStanfordUSA
  2. 2.Department of PsychologyUniversity of British ColumbiaVancouverCanada

Personalised recommendations