Skip to main content
  • 1457 Accesses

Abstract

Brouwer was extremely critical of Hilbert’s formalism, which was completely opposed to the intuitionistic philosophy of mathematics. Brouwer trod softly in his publications in order to avoid conflict. However, when Hermann Weyl joined Brouwer’s intuitionism, his ‘New crisis-paper’ the tone changed. Hilbert told Brouwer and Weyl in unmistakable terms how wrong they were. The Grundlagenstreit was born. The conflict dragged on for years.

From time to time the scientific discussion was replaced by external causes. One such was the planned publication of the Riemann memorial volume by the Mathematische Annalen. A conflict arose when the participation of French mathematicians could in this project of their arch enemy was questioned. One section of the editorial board objected to the French participation, which was advocated by Hilbert. The conflict left bad feelings.

Inspired by the contributions of Alexandrov, Menger, and Urysohn, Brouwer collected in 1925 a small group of topologists in Amsterdam, including Vietoris and Wilson. The brief concentration of topologists was later called the Dutch topological school.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Weyl to Mulder, 24.VII.1910.

  2. 2.

    See Sieg (1999).

  3. 3.

    Hilbert claimed that Kronecker rejected set theory on the grounds of the paradox of the set of all sets. This is rather a misjudgement of Kronecker’s motives, moreover Kronecker died before the paradoxes surfaced.

  4. 4.

    Cf. Gray (2000), p. 248. Brouwer was indeed quick to point out this shift, Brouwer (1919h).

  5. 5.

    Brouwer (1919a).

  6. 6.

    There are certain indications that Hilbert’s independent position during the war had made him no friends among his colleagues. Born wrote in a letter to Hilbert (27.VIII.1919) that he guessed that Hilbert’s action was largely determined by his relationship with the ‘Göttingen’ colleagues, who mostly subscribed to the Alldeutschtum. In view of the treatment by this group during the war, Hilbert’s threat to leave Göttingen might not have been empty talk.

  7. 7.

    Brouwer (1919h, 1922a).

  8. 8.

    See Sect. 8.8.

  9. 9.

    Since there is no elaboration of this remark, one can only make an educated guess as to what these similarities were. A possible candidate could be Weyl’s treatment of quantified statements as ‘judgement abstracts’. In Hilbert’s writings a similar phenomenon surfaces in the distinction between finitary, meaningful statements and quantified, ideal statements, cf. Hilbert (1926), p. 174. In Hilbert’s papers no reference to Weyl’s ideas is to be found. There is, however, a reference in Hilbert and Bernays (1934, 1939).

  10. 10.

    Festschrift udgivet af Københavns Universitet. November 1921, p. 114.

  11. 11.

    Natur und mathematisches Erkennen (March 14), Axiomenlehre und Widerspruchsfreiheit (15 and 17 March). I am indebted to Sigurd Elkjaer for the information and documentation on Hilbert’s Copenhagen lectures and doctorate.

  12. 12.

    See Hesseling (2002) for details.

  13. 13.

    Hilbert (1922).

  14. 14.

    Cf. p. 313.

  15. 15.

    Hilbert (1922), p. 159.

  16. 16.

    Cf. p. 314 ff.

  17. 17.

    Cf. pp. 313, 313.

  18. 18.

    Cf. Poincaré (1905), Les derniers efforts des Logisticiens, Poincaré (1908) (livre II, Chaps. IV, V), Brouwer (1907), p. 172.

  19. 19.

    Kneser (1925).

  20. 20.

    Brouwer (1923b, 1923f), translated in van Heijenoort (1967).

  21. 21.

    Abbreviated as PEM, principle of the excluded middle.

  22. 22.

    Brouwer (1923f), p. 2.

  23. 23.

    Brouwer (1919h).

  24. 24.

    In Fraenkel (1923), p. 239, Brouwer is quoted slightly differently: ‘For intuitionists, however, ‘consistency’ has by no means the same meaning as ‘existence’, no more than ‘a crime which’ cannot be detected by prescribed means of investigation stops being a crime.’

  25. 25.

    Brouwer (1907), p. 138 (footnote), pp. 141, 142.

  26. 26.

    Cf. I.10.4, p. 392. Brouwer had picked a hard, although elementary, problem. Only in 1998 was the sequence 0123456789 found in the decimal expansion of π, Borwein (1998). Needless to say that the demise of a single counterexample does not weaken the intuitionist cause—there are enough new counterexamples.

  27. 27.

    The trichotomy property asserts the comparability of any two elements: xyyx. Brouwer’s favourite formulation was ‘the continuum cannot be ordered’, Brouwer (1950, 1992).

  28. 28.

    Cf. p. 386; see van Dalen (2000) for more on Fraenkel and intuitionism.

  29. 29.

    Einleitung in die Mengenlehre, Fraenkel (1919).

  30. 30.

    Knopp to Fraenkel, 2.I.1924.

  31. 31.

    Fraenkel (1923), p. 164.

  32. 32.

    Fraenkel (1923), p. 173.

  33. 33.

    See p. 386.

  34. 34.

    Hilbert (1923).

  35. 35.

    Fraenkel (1923), p. 239.

  36. 36.

    Belinfante (1923).

  37. 37.

    Belinfante had not made use of Brouwer’s new results, such as the fan theorem and the continuity theorem. From a modern point of view, one could say that he belonged to the Bishop school avant la lettre.

  38. 38.

    Brouwer and de Loor (1924), Brouwer (1924a, 1924b, 1924c, 1924d).

  39. 39.

    Weitzenböck to Weyl, 16.IV.1923.

  40. 40.

    Brouwer to Bieberbach, 1924, undated. See p. 406.

  41. 41.

    Konsequenzen des intuitionistischen Standpunktes in der Mathematik.

  42. 42.

    Reid (1970), p. 184.

  43. 43.

    Since Blumenthal, Brouwer and Klein were at the time entangled in the unpleasant Mohrmann affair, there was no shortage of topics, see also p. 583.

  44. 44.

    In the same letter he told of his strongly favourable impression of Kneser and Neugebauer.

  45. 45.

    Reid (1970), p. 184.

  46. 46.

    Drost (1952), p. 26.

  47. 47.

    Brouwer (1929b).

  48. 48.

    1921—1; 1923—4; 1924—7, 1925—2; 1926—2; 1927—3; 1928—2; 1929—1 (not counting the multiple versions).

  49. 49.

    Interview, A. Heyting.

  50. 50.

    Ziffernkomplex. In Brouwer (1925a) Brouwer used ‘Nummer’.

  51. 51.

    e.g. Brouwer (1954a).

  52. 52.

    Brouwer (1925a).

  53. 53.

    Strictly speaking one particular second-order restriction had been implicitly recognised all along, namely the restriction of all future choices to a law.

  54. 54.

    These sequences were later independently introduced by Kreisel as ‘lawless sequences’, cf. Kreisel (1968). See also Troelstra (1982).

  55. 55.

    Brouwer (1942a).

  56. 56.

    Cambridge Lectures 1946–1950, Brouwer (1981).

  57. 57.

    Of higher-order restriction.

  58. 58.

    Brouwer (1981), p. 13.

  59. 59.

    Brouwer (1952b), p. 142. Indeed, higher-order restrictions in general destroy not only the simplicity, but put the continuity principle in danger. See van Atten and van Dalen (2002).

  60. 60.

    See Hesseling (1999).

  61. 61.

    Hilbert 1904, reprinted in the later versions of Grundlagen der Geometrie.

  62. 62.

    See p. 125

  63. 63.

    Brouwer (1928b).

  64. 64.

    Cf. Sieg (1999, 2000).

  65. 65.

    Bernstein (1919), pp. 63–78.

  66. 66.

    Bernays (1922), submitted 13.X.1921. Translations of many of the key publications of this period can be found in Mancosu (1998). See also van Heijenoort (1967).

  67. 67.

    Bernays (1922), p. 11.

  68. 68.

    Ibid. p. 10.

  69. 69.

    Ibid. p. 15.

  70. 70.

    That is to say, Bernays pointed out in his writings, cf. Bernays (1922), that Hilbert did not lack in appreciation for constructive metamathematics. For some reason Hilbert just did not see, or did not wish to see, his intellectual debt to Brouwer and Weyl.

  71. 71.

    The terminology is anachronistic; Brouwer started to use the name ‘intuitionism’ for his program after World War I.

  72. 72.

    Brouwer (1907), Chap. 3.

  73. 73.

    Hilbert (1922).

  74. 74.

    Cf. Rowe (1989).

  75. 75.

    Grundlagen der Mathematik I (1934), II (1939).

  76. 76.

    See p. 442. Brouwer’s Nauheim lecture predates the Grundlagenstreit; it is by all standards a totally innocuous academic treatise on effective procedures, without programmatic claims. Nobody could possibly take exception to it. Therefore I will not view it as part of the foundational conflict.

  77. 77.

    See p. 445.

  78. 78.

    Curiously enough Brouwer was in Münster on June 1 and 2. At least that was what Brouwer announced in a letter to Gerda Holdert, 14.V.1925: ‘I have to be in Münster on June 1, 2.’ He may or may not have gone to Münster after all, but it remains a curious coincidence.

  79. 79.

    Über das Unendliche und die Begründung der Mathematik.

  80. 80.

    Hilbert (1926), p. 163.

  81. 81.

    Ibid. p. 170.

  82. 82.

    The fact that Hilbert accepted the modest constructive approach: potential infinite for cardinalities in the style of Brouwer 1907, of course does not imply that he would accept, or even contemplate, choice sequences.

  83. 83.

    Hilbert (1923), p. 160.

  84. 84.

    Hilbert used the German ‘finit’ instead of ‘endlich’. Following Kleene, the term finitary has been adopted in the foundations of mathematics.

  85. 85.

    Hilbert (1926), p. 179. A more modern version would run roughly as follows: if a finitary statement is provable in the extended system, then it is already provable in the finitary system (the extension is conservative).

  86. 86.

    Courant to Hilbert, 10.IX.1925.

  87. 87.

    Cf. Schroeder-Gudehus (1966), p. 199, Schmidt-Ott (1952).

  88. 88.

    See p. 332.

  89. 89.

    Brouwer to Blumenthal, 1.XI.1924.

  90. 90.

    Cf. p. 329.

  91. 91.

    The editorial board contained two kinds of editors: the proper editors, listed on the cover as ‘Herausgeber’ (publishers), and associated editors, listed under the heading ‘unter Mitwirkung von’ (with the co-operation of). When relevant, we will call the first kind ‘managing editors’ and the second kind ‘associate editors’.

  92. 92.

    Carathéodory to Brouwer, 6.XI.1924.

  93. 93.

    ohne Gefahr zu laufen, von der ganzen Meute der Banausen angebellt zu werden.’

  94. 94.

    Blumenthal to Einstein, 15.XII.1924.

  95. 95.

    Einstein to Blumenthal, 16.XII.1924.

  96. 96.

    Bieberbach to Blumenthal, 12.I.1925.

  97. 97.

    Hölder to Blumenthal, 13.I.1925.

  98. 98.

    Einstein to Blumenthal, 20.I.1925.

  99. 99.

    wenn absolute Beweise deutschfreundlicher Gesinnung und Betätigung vorliegen’.

  100. 100.

    Carathéodory to Blumenthal, 20.I.1925.

  101. 101.

    Cf. p. 627.

  102. 102.

    Bieberbach to Blumenthal, 23.I.1925.

  103. 103.

    Bieberbach to Hilbert, 25.II.1925.

  104. 104.

    Cf. p. 551.

  105. 105.

    Minutes of the meeting of the Wiskundig Genootschap of 24.II.1923.

  106. 106.

    In 1924 Einstein joined the C.C.I., an organisation of the League of Nations, after all. The larger part of my information on the scientific organisations after the war is drawn from Schröder-Gudehus’ books, Schroeder-Gudehus (1966, 1978), which are highly recommended for their treatment and the use of sources.

  107. 107.

    Karo (1926). It is worth noting that Karo was a Jew, and that he emigrated to the USA during the Nazi period. The protest against the boycott of German science and scientists was supported by a large section of the German academic community.

  108. 108.

    The motto is: Je maintiendrai.

  109. 109.

    Schroeder-Gudehus (1966), p. 248.

  110. 110.

    Kerkhof to Brouwer, 4.V.1925.

  111. 111.

    Brouwer to Kerkhof, 11.V.1925.

  112. 112.

    Witness the remark of Sommerfeld in a letter to Blumenthal (26.I.1925): ‘I can but experience it as humiliating that Brouwer feels more German than we do.’

  113. 113.

    Cf. Schroeder-Gudehus (1966), p. 207.

  114. 114.

    Cf. p. 329.

  115. 115.

    Der geistige Krieg gegen Deutschland, Karo (1926).

  116. 116.

    As testified by letters in the Alexandrov archive.

  117. 117.

    Alexandrov (1980), p. 322 ff., Menger (1979), p. 241, ff.

  118. 118.

    Smid became a specialist in insurance mathematics. Max Euwe won in 1935 the world title in chess. Later he became a professor in computer science.

  119. 119.

    Brouwer actually lived most of the time in Blaricum, but right at the border with Laren. This border has moved back and forth in the course of time. Sometimes he rented a house in Laren or in Blaricum. A large part of his letters bears the name of Laren, later letters show Blaricum.

  120. 120.

    Interview Van der Waerden.

  121. 121.

    Oral communication F. Kuiper.

  122. 122.

    Max Euwe told a different story. When Van der Waerden asked his question, Brouwer replied sternly and then concluded: ‘Mr. Van der Waerden, I advise you to study the material completely before you start a discussion.’ The story went from student generation to student generation. Freudenthal’s version was that ‘Van der Waerden thought to have found a mistake. But Brouwer was completely right.’

  123. 123.

    Emmy Noether to Brouwer, 14.XI.1925.

  124. 124.

    ‘The algebraic foundations of the geometry of number’, [i.e. enumerative geometry], van der Waerden (1926).

  125. 125.

    de Vries (1936).

  126. 126.

    For biographical information on Van der Waerden, see Springer (1997) and the papers in Nieuw Archief voor Wiskunde, 1994(12) no. 3.

  127. 127.

    Oral communication Gerda Holdert.

  128. 128.

    Menger to Brouwer, 3.VII.1925.

  129. 129.

    L.E.J. Brouwer in tiefer Verehrung gewidmet.

  130. 130.

    Menger (1979).

  131. 131.

    Here and in the following pages I quote from Menger (1979).

  132. 132.

    Alexandrov (1969), p. 117.

  133. 133.

    Die Topologie in und um Holland in den Jahren 1920–1930, Alexandrov (1969).

  134. 134.

    Cf. MacLane (1981).

  135. 135.

    E. Noether to Brouwer, 7.1X.1919. For the Karlsruhe meeting, see p. 175 ff.

  136. 136.

    Brouwer to E. Noether, 21.XI.1925.

  137. 137.

    The University of Göttingen.

  138. 138.

    Alexandrov to E. Noether, 11.XI.1925.

  139. 139.

    Rectal, as the hospital tradition was.

  140. 140.

    Oral communication, Mrs. J.F. Heyting-van Anrooy.

  141. 141.

    Alexandrov to Hopf, 10.IV.1927.

  142. 142.

    We recall that Urysohn discussed his dimension theory for the first time (with Alexandrov) in August 1921 (cf. p. 397 and Johnson 1981, p. 228). He lectured on the topic in Moscow in the academic year 1921/22, and submitted three printed notes on the subject to the Moscow Mathematical Society. The first internationally accessible version appeared in the Comptes Rendus in 1922. Menger developed his ideas on dimension theory between April 1921 ands February 1922. An account was submitted to Hahn in November 1922, and was withdrawn after Hahn discovered a mistake in it. Menger’s first publication followed in December 1923, Menger (1923).

  143. 143.

    Menger to Brouwer, 10.IV.1926.

  144. 144.

    Schreier to Menger, 7.IV.1926.

  145. 145.

    Hahn to Brouwer, 10.IV.1926. It is not clear whether Menger or Brouwer asked for this information.

  146. 146.

    Menger (1926).

  147. 147.

    Brouwer to Hahn, 22.X.1929.

  148. 148.

    Brouwer (1976), p. 567.

  149. 149.

    Brouwer was off to Batz, to meet Alexandrov.

  150. 150.

    Menger to Brouwer, 19.VIII.1926.

  151. 151.

    In oprechte waardering van Uw werk en in dankbaarheid U opgedragen van den schrijver. Menger had for all practical purposes mastered the Dutch language.

  152. 152.

    Brouwer to Hahn, 27.VIII.1929.

  153. 153.

    Brouwer to Hahn, 22.X.1929.

  154. 154.

    Menger (1979), p. 246.

  155. 155.

    One can sympathise with Menger, although my experiences were the other way round. When I first learned about analytic sets, I thought, ‘Why, these are spreads!’

  156. 156.

    Menger (1979), pp. 86, 246.

  157. 157.

    Menger (1928a), ‘Über Verzweigungsmengen’, translated in Menger (1979) as ‘An intuitionistic-formalistic dictionary of set theory’. See also Menger (2003), pp. 3–22.

  158. 158.

    See Menger (2003), p. 4.

  159. 159.

    Heyting (1931b).

  160. 160.

    Brouwer to Hahn, 22.X.1929.

  161. 161.

    For comparison, here are the two formulations: Menger—‘in einem allerdings weniger bekannten kurzen Aufsatz (Crelle Journ. 142, S.146–152) eine Definition n-dimensionaler Kontinua gegeben, die nach Korrektur (Amsterdamer Akademieber. XXVI, 1923) mit unserer Definition des n-dimensionalen Kontinuums äquivalent ist’; Brouwer—‘in einem allerdings weniger bekannten kurzen Aufsatz (Journ.f.Math. 142, S.146–152; vgl. auch die Korrektur eines daselbst befindlichen Schreibfehlers in den Amsterdamer Proceedings 26, S.796) eine Definition n-dimensionaler Kontinua gegeben, die mit unserem Definition des n-dimensionalen Kontinuums äquivalent ist.’ The reader will appreciate the difference in suggestive force.

  162. 162.

    Menger (1979), p. 247.

  163. 163.

    i.e. the theorem that ℝn has natural dimension n.

  164. 164.

    Cf. van Dalen (1999a), in which it is shown that, e.g., the irrationals (the complement of the rationals) are indecomposable, and hence 1-dimensional.

  165. 165.

    Alexandrov to Menger, 1925 (no precise date known).

  166. 166.

    Cf. Menger (1994), p. 200.

  167. 167.

    Tumarkin (1926), Menger to Brouwer, 8.IV.1927.

  168. 168.

    CW II, p. 564.

  169. 169.

    Enzyklopädie der mathematischen Wissenschaften, Dritter Band, Geometrie, Ch. 13. Enzyklopädie der mathematischen Wissenschaften (submitted 15.X.1929). In fact Klein had asked Brouwer to engage Vietoris to write the chapter. Alexandrov and Menger had opposed the idea (interview Vietoris).

  170. 170.

    Menger to Brouwer, 17.I.1928.

  171. 171.

    Geschichtliche Entwicklung der Topologie, Feigl (1928).

References

  • Alexandrov, P.S.: Die Topologie in und um Holland in den Jahren 1920–1930. Nieuw Arch. Wiskd. 17, 109–127 (1969)

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexandrov, P.S.: Pages from an autobiography. Russ. Math. Surv. 35, 315–358 (1980)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belinfante, M.J.: Over oneindige reeksen. Ph.D. thesis, Amsterdam (1923)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernays, P.: Über Hilbert’s Gedanken zur Grundlegung der Arithmetik. Jahresber. Dtsch. Math.-Ver. 31, 10–19 (1922)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, F.: Die Mengenlehre George Cantors und der Finitismus. Jahresber. Dtsch. Math.-Ver. 28, 63–78 (1919)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Borwein, J.M.: Brouwer–Heyting sequences converge. Math. Intell. 20, 14–15 (1998)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Over de grondslagen der wiskunde. Ph.D. thesis, Amsterdam (1907)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Begründung der Mengenlehre unabhängig vom logischen Satz vom ausgeschlossenen Dritten. Zweiter Teil, Theorie der Punktmengen. Verh. K. Akad. Wet. Amst. 7, 1–33 (1919a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Intuitionistische Mengenlehre. Jahresber. Dtsch. Math.-Ver. 28, 203–208 (1919h). Appeared in 1920

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Intuitionistische Mengenlehre. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 23, 949–954 (1922a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Over de rol van het principium tertiï exclusi in the wiskunde, in het bijzonder in de functietheorie. Wis- Natuurkd. Tijdschr. 2, 1–7 (1923b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Über die Bedeutung des Satzes vom ausgeschlossenen Dritten in der Mathematik insbesondere in der Funktionentheorie. J. Reine Angew. Math. 154, 1–8 (1923f)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Beweis dass jede volle Funktion gleichmässig stetig ist. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 27, 189–193 (1924a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Intuitionistische Ergänzung des Fundamentalsatzes der Algebra. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 27, 631–634 (1924b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Bewijs van de onafhankelijkheid van de onttrekkingsrelatie van de versmeltingsrelatie. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Versl. Gewone Vergad. Afd. Natuurkd. 33, 479–480 (1924c)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Bemerkungen zum Beweise der gleichmässigen Stetigkeit voller Funktionen. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 27, 644–646 (1924d)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Zur Begründung der intuitionistischen Mathematik I. Math. Ann. 93, 244–257 (1925a). Corr. in Brouwer (1926a)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Intuitionistische Betrachtungen über den Formalismus. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 31, 374–379 (1928b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Zur Geschichtsschreibung der Dimensionstheorie. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 31, 953–957 (1928f). Corr. in KNAW Proc. 32, p. 1022

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Herinnering aan C.S. Aama van Scheltema door L.E.J. Brouwer, p. 69. Querido, Amsterdam (1929b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Zum freien Werden von Mengen und Funktionen. Indag. Math. 4, 107–108 (1942a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Sur la possibilité d’ordonner le continu. C. R. Math. Acad. Sci. Paris 230, 349–350 (1950)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Historical background, principles and methods of intuitionism. South Afr. J. Sci. 49, 139–146 (1952b)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Point and spaces. Can. J. Math. 6, 1–17 (1954a)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Collected Works 2. Geometry, Analysis Topology and Mechanics. Freudenthal, H. (ed.). North-Holland, Amsterdam (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Brouwer’s Cambridge Lectures on Intuitionism. van Dalen, D. (ed.). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1981)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Intuitionismus. van Dalen, D. (ed.). Bibliographisches Institut Wissenschaftsverlag, Mannheim (1992)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J., de Loor, B.: Intuitionistischer Beweis des Fundamentalsatzes der Algebra. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 27, 186–188 (1924)

    Google Scholar 

  • de Vries, Hk.: Inleiding tot de studie der meetkunde van het aantal. Noordhoff, Groningen (1936)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Drost, F.: Carel Steven Adama van Scheltema. Ph.D. thesis, Rijksuniversiteit Groningen (1952)

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, G.: Geschichtliche Entwicklung der Topologie. Jahresber. Dtsch. Math.-Ver. 37, 273–286 (1928)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Fraenkel, A.: Einleitung in die Mengenlehre. Springer, Berlin (1919)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Fraenkel, A.: Einleitung in die Mengenlehre, 2nd edn. Springer, Berlin, (1923)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Gray, J.J.: The Hilbert Challenge. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2000)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Hesseling, D.E.: Gnomes in the fog. The reception of Brouwer’s intuitionism in the 1920s. Ph.D. thesis, Utrecht (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesseling, D.E.: Gnomes in the Fog. The Reception of Brouwer’s Intuitionism in the 1920s. Birkhäuser, Basel (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyting, A.: Philosphische Grundlegung der Mathematik. Blätter für Deutsche Philosophie (4), 1930 (review). Jahresber. Dtsch. Math.-Ver. 40, 50–52 (1931b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D.: Neubegründung der Mathematik (Erste Mitteilung). Abh. Math. Semin. Univ. Hamb. 1, 157–177 (1922)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D.: Die Logischen Grundlagen der Mathematik. Math. Ann. 88, 151–165 (1923)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D.: Über das Unendliche. Math. Ann. 95, 161–190 (1926)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D., Bernays, P.: Grundlagen der Mathematik I. Springer, Berlin (1934)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D., Bernays, P.: Grundlagen der Mathematik II. Springer, Berlin (1939)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, D.M.: The problem of the invariance of dimension in the growth of modern topology, part II. Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 25, 85–267 (1981)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Karo, G.: Der geistige Krieg gegen Deutschland. Z. Völkerpsychol. Soziol. 2 (1926), 22 pp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kneser, A.: Leopold Kronecker. Jahresber. Dtsch. Math.-Ver. 33, 210–228 (1925)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Kreisel, G.: Lawless sequences of natural numbers. Compos. Math. 20, 222–248 (1968)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • MacLane, S.: Mathematics at the University of Göttingen, 1931–1933. In: Brewer, J., Smith, M. (eds.) Emmy Noether: A Tribute to Her Life and Work, pp. 65–78. Marcel Dekker, New York (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P.: From Brouwer to Hilbert. The Debate on the Foundations of Mathematics in the 1920s. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1998). Collection of papers

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Menger, K.: Über die Dimensionalität von Punktmengen. I. Monatshefte Math. Phys. 33, 148–160 (1923)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Menger, K.: Zur Entstehung meiner Arbeiten über Dimensions- und Kurventheorie. Proc. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. 29, 1122–1124 (1926). Subm. 29.5.1926

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Menger, K.: Bemerkungen zu Grundlagenfragen. Jahresber. Dtsch. Math.-Ver. 37, 213–226 (1928a). On the analogy Spreads-Analytic sets

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Menger, K.: Selected Papers in Logic and Foundations, Didactics, Economics. Reidel, Dordrecht (1979)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Menger, K.: Reminiscences of the Vienna Circle and the Mathematical Colloquium. Golland, L., McGuinness, B., Sklar, A. (eds.). Kluwer, Dordrecht (1994)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Menger, K.: Selecta Mathematica. Schweizer, B., Sklar, A., Sigmund, K., Gruber, P., Hlawka, E., Reich, L., Schmetterer, L. (eds.). Springer, Vienna (2003)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H.: Science et Méthode. Flammarion, Paris (1905)

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H.: L’Avenir des mathématiques. In: Castelnuovo, G. (ed.) Atti IV Congr. Intern. Mat. Roma, vol. 1, pp. 167–182. Accad. Naz. Lincei, Roma (1908)

    Google Scholar 

  • Reid, C.: Hilbert. Springer, Berlin (1970)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, D.E.: Interview with Dirk Jan Struik. Math. Intell. 11, 14–26 (1989)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt-Ott, F.: Erlebtes und Erstrebtes. 1860–1950. Franz Steiner Verlag, Wiesbaden (1952)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder-Gudehus, B.: Deutsche Wissenschaft und internationale Zusammenarbeit, 1914–1928. Ein Beitrag zum Studium kultureller Beziehungen in politischen Krisenzeiten. Imprimerie Dumaret & Golay, Geneve (1966)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder-Gudehus, B.: Les Scientifiques et la Paix. La communauté scientifique internationale au cours des années 20. Les Presses de l’Université de Montréal, Montréal (1978)

    Google Scholar 

  • Sieg, W.: Hilbert’s programs: 1917–1922. Bull. Symb. Log. 5, 1–44 (1999)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Sieg, W.: Towards finitist proof theory. In: Jørgensen, K.F., Hendricks, V., Pedersen, S.A. (eds.) Proof Theory. History and Philosophical Significance. Synthese Library, vol. 292, pp. 95–116. Kluwer, Dordrecht (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  • Springer, T.A.: B.L. van der Waerden. Levensber. Herdenk. 999, 45–50 (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  • Troelstra, A.S.: On the origin and development of Brouwer’s concept of choice sequence. In: Troelstra, A.S., van Dalen, D. (eds.) The L.E.J. Brouwer Centenary Symposium, vol. 999, pp. 465–486. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1982)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tumarkin, L.: Nouvelle démonstration d’un théorème de Paul Urysohn. Fundam. Math. 8, 360–361 (1926)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • van Atten, M., van Dalen, D.: Arguments for the continuity principle. Bull. Symb. Log. 8, 329–347 (2002)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • van Dalen, D.: From Brouwerian counter examples to the creating subject. Stud. Log. 62, 305–314 (1999a)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • van Dalen, D.: Brouwer and Fraenkel on intuitionism. Bull. Symb. Log. 6, 284–310 (2000)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • van der Waerden, B.L.: De algebraiese grondslagen der meetkunde van het aantal. Ph.D. thesis, University of Amsterdam (1926)

    Google Scholar 

  • van Heijenoort, J.: From Frege to Gödel. A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1967)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer-Verlag London

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

van Dalen, D. (2013). Progress, Recognition, and Frictions. In: L.E.J. Brouwer – Topologist, Intuitionist, Philosopher. Springer, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4471-4616-2_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics