Advertisement

The Social Embedding of Intelligence

Towards Producing a Machine that Could Pass the Turing Test
  • Bruce Edmonds

Abstract

I claim that to pass the Turing Test over any period of extended time, it will be necessary to embed the entity into society. This chapter discusses why this is, and how it might be brought about. I start by arguing that intelligence is better characterized by tests of social interaction, especially in open-ended and extended situations. I then argue that learning is an essential component of intelligence and hence that a universal intelligence is impossible. These two arguments support the relevance of the Turing Test as a particular, but appropriate test of interactive intelligence. I look to the human case to argue that individual intelligence uses society to a considerable extent for its development. Taking a lead from the human case, I outline how a socially embedded Artificial Intelligence might be brought about in terms of four aspects: free will, emotion, empathy, and self-modeling. In each case, I try to specify what social ‘hooks’ might be required for the full ability to develop during a considerable period of in situ acculturation. The chapter ends by speculating what it might be like to live with the result.

Keywords

Intelligence social embedding interaction free will empathy self emotion Turing Test learning design acculturation 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Aydede, M., 1999, Language of thought hypothesis: state of the art, in: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy; http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/language-thought/.
  2. Aydede, M. and Güzeldere, G., 2002, Consciousness, intentionality, and intelligence: some foundational issues for artificial intelligence; http://web.clas.ufl.edu/users/maydede/introspection.htm.
  3. Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A.M., et al., 1985, Does the autistic child have a ‘theory of mind’? Cognition 21: 37–46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Baum, E., 1998, Manifesto for an Evolutionary Economics of Intelligence, in: B., Neural Networks and Machine Learning, Springer, pp. 285–344.Google Scholar
  5. Bridgeman, B., 1992, On the evolution of consciousness and language, Pscoloquy3; http://www.cogsci.soton.ac.uk/cgi/psyc/newpsy?3.15.
  6. Brooks, R. A., 1991, Intelligence without representation, Artificial Intelligence 47(1–3): 139–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Burns, T. R. and Engdahl, E., 1998, The social construction of consciousness part 2: individual selves, self-awareness, and reflectivity, Journal of Consciousness Studies 2: 166–184.Google Scholar
  8. Byrne, R. W. and Whiten, A., 1988, Machiavellian Intelligence: Social Expertise and the Evolution of Intellect in Monkeys, Apes and Humans, Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
  9. Byrne, R. W. and Whiten, A., 1997, Machiavellian Intelligence II: Extensions and Evaluations, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  10. Dautenhahn, K., 1997, I could be you: the phenomenological dimension of social understanding, Cybernetics and Systems 28: 417–453.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Dennett, D. C., 1984, Elbow Room: The Varieties of Free Will Worth Wanting, Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
  12. Dennett, D. C., 1989, The origin of selves, Cogito 3(163–173).Google Scholar
  13. Drescher, G. L., 1991, Made-up Minds – A Constructivist Approach to Artificial Intelligence, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.zbMATHGoogle Scholar
  14. Edmonds, B., 1999a, Capturing social embeddedness: a constructivist approach, Adaptive Behavior 7(3–4): 323–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Edmonds, B., 1999b, Gossip, sexual recombination and the el farol bar: modelling the emergence of heterogeneity, Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation 2(3).Google Scholar
  16. Edmonds, B., 2000, The constructability of artificial intelligence (as defined by the Turing Test), Journal of Logic Language and Information 9: 419–424.zbMATHCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Edmonds, B., 2001 Meta-genetic programming: co-evolving the operators of variation, Elektrik 9(1): 13–29.Google Scholar
  18. Ernst, G. and Newell, A., 1969, GPS: A Case Study in Generality and Problem Solving, Academic Press, New York.Google Scholar
  19. French, R. M., 1990, Subcognition and the limits of the Turing test, Mind 99: 53–65.CrossRefMathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  20. Goldberg, D. E., Deb, K., et al., 1989, Messy genetic algorithms: motivation, analysis, and first results, Complex Systems 3: 493–530.zbMATHMathSciNetGoogle Scholar
  21. Gopnik, A., 1993, How we know our minds: the illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality, Behavioural and Brain Sciences 16: 1–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Hendriks-Jansen, H., 1997, The epistomology of autism: making a case for an embodied, dynamic, and historic explanation, Cybernetics and Systems 28: 359–416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Hoffman, J., 1993, Vorhersage und Erkenntnis [Anticipation and Cognition], Hogrefe, Goettingen, Germany.Google Scholar
  24. Hofstadter, D. R., 1985, Analogies and roles in human and machine thinking, in: Metamagical Themas: Questing for the Essence of Mind and Pattern, Penguin, London.Google Scholar
  25. Holland, J. H., 1992, Adaptation in Natural and Artificial Systems, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  26. Jannink, J., 1994, Cracking and co-evolving randomlist, in: Advances in Genetic Programming, K. E. Kinnear, ed., MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  27. Koza, J. R., 1992, Genetic Programming: On the Programming of Computers by Means of Natural Selection, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.zbMATHGoogle Scholar
  28. Koza, J. R., 1994, Genetic Programming II: Automatic Discovery of Reusable Subprograms, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  29. Kummer, H., Daston, L., Gigerenzer, G., and Silk, J., 1997, The social intelligence hypothesis, in: Human by Nature: Between Biology and the Social Sciences, Weingart et al., eds., Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, pp. 157–179.Google Scholar
  30. Minsky, M., 2002, The emotion machine; http://web.media.mit.edu/˜minsky/
  31. Perlis, D., 1997, Consciousness as self-function, Journal of Consciousness Studies 4: 509–525.Google Scholar
  32. Rolls, E. T., 2000, Precis of the brain and emotion, Behavioural and Brain Sciences 23(2): 177–191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Sloman, A., 2002, How many separately evolved emotional beasties live within us?, in: P. S. Emotions in Humans and Artifacts, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  34. Stolzmann, W., 1998, Anticipatory Classifier Systems, Genetic Programming, University of Wisconsin, Morgan Kaufmann, Madison, WI, pp. 658–664.Google Scholar
  35. Tolman, E. C., 1932, Purposive Behavior in Animals and Men, Appleton, New York.Google Scholar
  36. Weizenbaum, J., 1976, Computer Power and Human Reason: From Judgement to Calculation, W. H. Freeman, San Francisco, CAGoogle Scholar
  37. Wolpert, D. H. and Macready, W. G., 1995, No free lunch theorems for search, Santa Fe Institute Technical Report SFI-TR-95–02–010.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009

Authors and Affiliations

  • Bruce Edmonds
    • 1
  1. 1.Centre for Policy ModellingManchester Metropolitan UniversityManchesterUSA

Personalised recommendations