Advertisement

Abstract

‘A modern philosopher who has never experienced the feeling of being a charlatan is such a shallow mind that his work is probably not worth reading.’1 So states Leszek Kolakowski at the very start of a work on modern philosophy. His acerbic comment is no doubt true, but it some-what misses the real point, for it implies what can no longer be taken for granted: that there still is a clear differentiation to be drawn between those philosophers who are worth reading, the geniuses presumably, and those who are mere charlatans. In effect, he maintains that any modern philosopher who has never doubted himself sufficiently to entertain the possibility of being a charlatan is most probably in fact a charlatan. But most of the widely read and acclaimed modern philosophers were not given to such self-doubts. Despite this, one cannot castigate them as simply charlatans either.

Keywords

Vienna Circle Class Consciousness Worth Reading Early Philosophy Religious Character 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. 1.
    Leszek Kolakowski, Metaphysical Horror (Blackwell, Oxford, 1981), p. 1.Google Scholar
  2. 4.
    John van Buren, The Young Heidegger: Rumour of the Hidden King (Indiana, University Press, Bloomington, 1994), p. 385.Google Scholar
  3. 6.
    Martin Heidegger, Der Spiegel, May 1976 (interview of 1966).Google Scholar
  4. 7.
    See C.G. Luckhard (ed.), Wittgenstein: Sources and Perspectives (Harvester Press, Brighton, 1979), p. 54.Google Scholar
  5. 8.
    Ludwig Wittgenstein, Letters to Russell, Keynes and Moore, ed. G.H. von Wright (Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY, 1974), p. 136.Google Scholar
  6. 9.
    J.M. Findlay, Wittgenstein: A Critique (Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1984), p. 21.Google Scholar
  7. 10.
    Lucien Goldmann, Lukács and Heidegger: Towards a New Philosophy, trans. W.Q. Boelhower (Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1977), pp. 16–17.Google Scholar
  8. 11.
    Giovanni Gentile, La Religione: Discorsi di religione (Sansoni, Firenze, 1965), p. 431.Google Scholar
  9. 12.
    Ferenc Feher and Agnes Heller, The Grandeur and Twilight of Radical Universalism (Transactions Publisher, New Brunswick, 1991), p. 554.Google Scholar
  10. 13.
    G. Neske and E. Kettering (eds.), Martin Heidegger and National Socialism (Paragon House, New York, 1990), p. 143.Google Scholar
  11. 15.
    Brian McGuiness (ed.), Wittgenstein and his Times (Blackwell, Oxford, 1982), p. 41.Google Scholar
  12. 16.
    Jader Jacobelli, Croce: Gentile, Dal solidazio al dramma (Rizzoli, Milano, 1989), pp. 203–4.Google Scholar
  13. 17.
    Quoted in Richard Wolin (ed.), The Heidegger Controversy (Columbia University Press, New York, 1991), p. 178.Google Scholar
  14. 18.
    Primo Siena (ed.), Gentile (Volpe Editore, Roma, 1966), p. 86.Google Scholar
  15. 20.
    Charles Guignon (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger (Cambridge University Press, New York, 1993), p. 76.Google Scholar
  16. 22.
    Árpad Kadarkay, Georg Lukács (Blackwell, Oxford, 1991), p. 121.Google Scholar
  17. 23.
    Karl Jaspers, Notizen zu Heidegger, ed. Hans Saner (R. Piper Verlag, Zürich, 1978), p. 213.Google Scholar
  18. 24.
    Michael Löwy, Georg Lukács — From Romanticism to Bolshevism (NLB, London, 1979), p. 55.Google Scholar
  19. 25.
    Martin Heidegger, quoted by Theodor Kisiel, ‘Heidegger’s Apology’, in T. Rockmore and J. Margolis(eds.), The Heidegger Case: On Philosophy and Politics (Temple University Press, Philadelphia, 1991), p. 134.Google Scholar
  20. 26.
    Quoted in Charles L. Creegan, Wittgenstein and Kierkegaard (Routledge, London, 1989), p. 15.Google Scholar
  21. 29.
    Karl Löwith, Nature, History and Existentialism (Northwestern University Press, Evanston, Ill. 1966), p. 55.Google Scholar
  22. 33.
    Giovanni Gentile, Theory of Mind as Pure Act, trans. H. Wildon Carr (Macmillan, London, 1923), p. xi.Google Scholar
  23. 35.
    Friedrich Waismann, Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle, ed. Brian McGuiness (Blackwell, Oxford, 1979).Google Scholar
  24. 36.
    Karl Löwith, My Life in Germany, before and after 1933, ‘Curriculum Vitae’ (1959), trans. E. King (University of Illinois Press, Urbana and Chicago, 1994), p. 150.Google Scholar
  25. 37.
    Max Weber, ‘Science as a Vocation’, in From Max Weber, ed. H.H. Gerth and C.W. Mills (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1951), p. 129.Google Scholar
  26. 41.
    H.S. Harris, The Social Philosophy of Giovanni Gentile (University of Illinois Press, Urbana, 1960), p. 284.Google Scholar
  27. 43.
    Richard Wolin, The Politics of Being (Columbia University Press, New York, 1990), pp. 71–2.Google Scholar
  28. 44.
    W.J. Richardson, Heidegger: Through Phenomenology to Thought (Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, 1967) p. xvi.Google Scholar
  29. 47.
    Quoted in George Pitcher (ed.), The Philosophy of Wittgenstein (Macmillan, London, 1964), p. 8.Google Scholar
  30. 48.
    Ray Monk, Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius (Vintage, London, 1990), p. 295.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Harry Redner 1997

Authors and Affiliations

  • Harry Redner

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations