Skip to main content
  • 12 Accesses

Abstract

In dialectical argument the questioner’s role, generally speaking, is that of an attacker of the thesis maintained by the answerer. In the dialectical debates of Aristotle’s time, for which the Topics and the Sophistical Elenchi are analyses and guides, and in the academic disputations in the schools from the Middle Ages until the nineteenth century, the questioner (opponent) had the responsibility of securing propositions, some of which were accepted as obviously true by the answerer (respondent, who defended the received opinion) and for others of which the answerer demanded syllogistic proof. The questioner accordingly framed a syllogism whose conclusion was the proposition he was trying to secure. If the syllogism seemed free of fallacy, and if the conclusion did not lie too near the contradictory of the thesis the answerer was defending, the answerer would concede the proposition which was the conclusion of the questioner’s syllogism. In order to triumph in the dialectical contest, the questioner had to secure two propositions which he then used as premises in another syllogism whose (necessary) conclusion the answerer and audience agreed followed without fallacy and which was in turn irrefutable by the answerer.1 The triumph lay in the questioner’s conclusion contradicting the thesis defended by the answerer.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 29.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. For commentary on the questioner-answerer concept of dialectic in Aristotle or in university disputations, see Charles Wesley, A Guide to Syllogism, … Comprehending an Account of the Manner of Disputation Now Practiced in the Schools at Cambridge (Cambridge, 1832) pp. 97–101

    Google Scholar 

  2. W. D. Ross, Aristotle (London: Methuen, 1923) p. 56

    Google Scholar 

  3. W. T. Costello, The Scholastic Curriculum at Early Seventeenth-Century Cambridge (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1958) pp. 20–4

    Book  Google Scholar 

  4. P. Moraux, ‘La joute dialectique d’après le huitième livre des Topiques’, Aristotle on Dialectic: The Topics, Proceedings of the Third Symposium Aristotelicum, ed. G. E. L. Owen (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968) esp. pp. 279–86; Gilbert Ryle, ‘Dialectic in the Academy’, ibid., p. 74.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Memoirs of Martinus Scriblerus, ed. C. Kerby-Miller (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1950) p. 118.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Schopenhauer, The Art of Controversy and Other Posthumous Papers, trans. T. B. Saunders (London: Swan Sonnenschein, 1896).pp. 4–5, 10.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Many of these kinds of argument are listed in C. L. Hamblin, Fallacies (London: Methuen, 1970) p. 41, and some are discussed, pp. 42–4.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Drapier’s Letters, p. 104. F. M. Cornford noticed the applicability of the argument ab utili to the academic world in his brief Microcosmographia Academica, Being a Guide for the Young Academic Politician (Cambridge, 1908; rpt. London: Bowes & Bowes, 1983) pp. 2–3.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Quoted in Drapier’s Letters, p. lxv. For a similar stratagem used by Swift against Godolphin over remission of First Fruits in Ireland, see D. Nokes, Jonathan Swift: A Hypocrite Reversed (Oxford University Press, 1985) pp. 89–91.

    Google Scholar 

  10. As did some academic disputations — see Christopher Wordsworth, Scholae Academicae (Cambridge University Press, 1877) p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  11. M. Price, Swift’s Rhetorical Art (New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press, 1953) pp. 94, 110

    Google Scholar 

  12. cf. H. D. Kelling, ‘Reason in Madness: A Tale of a Tub’, PMLA, 69 (1954), 216–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. By Chrysippus and the Stoic logicians. W. & M. Kneale, The Development of Logic (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962) p. 178.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Dilemma (δις, twice, two; λημμα, an assumption) was understood in the sixteenth, seventeenth and eighteenth centuries usually as an argument rather than as a practical predicament (see above, n. 41): Thomas Wilson, The Rule of Reason (1551; rpt. London, 1553) fol. 34v

    Google Scholar 

  15. Robert Sanderson, Logicae Artis Compendium, 9th ed. (Oxford, 1680) pp. 135–6

    Google Scholar 

  16. Burgersdicius, Institutionum Logicarum (Cambridge, 1680) p. 342

    Google Scholar 

  17. Narcissus March, Institutiones Logicae (Dublin, 1681) pp. 195–6.

    Google Scholar 

  18. It would naturally be defined as an argument in these and other logics of the time, but it was also defined as such in the dictionaries: Thomas Blount, Glossographia: or, a Dictionary … (London, 1656)

    Google Scholar 

  19. J. B., An English Expositour, Or Compleat Dictionary (Cambridge, 1684)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Edward Phillips, The New World of Words or, Universal English Dictionary, 6th ed. (London, 1706)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Nathaniel Bailey, An Universal Etymological Dictionary, 6th ed. (London, 1733)

    Google Scholar 

  22. ‘Dilemma’, defined in Burgersdicius, Monitio Logica: or an Abstract and Translation of Burgersdicius His Logick. By a Gentleman (London, 1697) p. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Henry Aldrich, Artis Logicae Compendium (Oxford, 1691) p. 29

    Google Scholar 

  24. Richard Whately, Elements of Logic, 6th ed. (London, 1836) p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Others accept the simple destructive as a valid form of a dilemma: G. H. Joyce, Principles of Logic, 2nd ed. (London: Longmans, Green, 1916) p. 210

    Google Scholar 

  26. S. H. Mellone, Elements of Modern Logic, 2nd ed. (London: University Tutorial Press, 1945) p. 168

    Google Scholar 

  27. M. R. Cohen and E. Nagel, An Introduction to Logic (Harbinger Books; New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1962) p. 106

    Google Scholar 

  28. S. F. Barker, The Elements of Logic (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1965) p. 98.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Referred to in Marsh p. 197; given as an example in Thomas Blundeville, The Art of Logike, 3rd ed. (London, 1619) p. 178; Burgersdicius’s Institutionum Logicarum, p. 201 and his Monitio Logica, p. 57; Joyce pp. 213–14

    Google Scholar 

  30. I. M. Copi, Introduction to Logic, 2nd ed. (New York: Macmillan, 1961) pp. 231–2.

    Google Scholar 

  31. ‘The message to Pilate from his wife furnishes an instance of a single word (“just”) suggesting a Major-premiss, while the Conclusion is stated in the form of an exhortation: “Have thou nothing to do with that just man”. And the succeeding sentence must have been designed to convey a hint of Arguments for the Proof of each of the Premises on which that Conclusion rested’: Whately, Elements of Logic, 9th ed. (London: Longmans, 1864) p. 78. The ref. is to Matt. 27: 19.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Thomas Sprat, The History of the Royal Society, ed. J. I. Cope and H. W. Jones (St Louis, Mo.: Washington University Studies, 1959) p. 354.

    Google Scholar 

  33. The ironic elements in this passage are mentioned in I. Ehrenpreis, ‘Swift and Satire’, College English, 13 (1952) 309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 1988 James A. W. Rembert

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rembert, J.A.W. (1988). Questioner against Answerer. In: Swift and the Dialectical Tradition. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-19072-0_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics