Advertisement

The Romantic Reaction

  • C. U. M. Smith
Chapter

Abstract

Man a Machine: a famous title, a famous book. La Mettrie, who published his work in 1748 (1), was in many ways a typical thinker of the European enlightenment. Like Voltaire, he attracted the wrath of churchmen. Like Voltaire, he was forced to flee from his orthodox enemies to a secular protector. Like Voltaire, he created enemies among his conservative countrymen by pointing out the seeming illogicalities of their thought, by poking fun at the absurdities in their intellectual position. And the conservatives, not as deeply schooled as they might have been, attempting to defend a position whose origins and structure had been almost forgotten, or perhaps never been made explicit, reacted with anger to hide their bafflement: reacted with anger at what seemed to be the easy superficiality of la Mettrie’s philosophy, and yet were mostly unable to show exactly where it was wrong and why it was not a profound alternative to their own thought. For la Mettrie seemed merely to have taken the Cartesian system to its logical terminus. Whereas Descartes conceived the living world to be composed of two categories of beings — animals which were (mere) mechanisms, and humans which had superadded to the mechanism a soul — la Mettrie saw animals and humans as one creation: machines all.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. (1).
    J.O. de la Mettrie, L’Homme Machine, Leyden (1748).Google Scholar
  2. (3).
    J-J. Rousseau, Discours sur l’Origine de L’Inégalité, Paris (1755); Classiques Larousse, Paris (1939), pp. 35–6.Google Scholar
  3. (4).
    W.Wordsworth, Lines Composed a Few Miles Above Tintern Abbey (1798).Google Scholar
  4. (5).
    Kant’s three important critiques — the Critique of Pure Reason (1781) (trans. J.M. D. Meiklejohn)Google Scholar
  5. (19).
    C.S.Sherrington, Goethe on Nature and on Science Cambridge University Press (1949).Google Scholar
  6. (20).
    L.Thorndike, A History of Magic and Experimental Science, (1929–1956), vol. 5, chapter 1.Google Scholar
  7. (21).
    J.W. von Goethe, Faust (trans. B. Taylor), World’s Classics Oxford University Press (1932), lines 1935–9.Google Scholar
  8. (23).
    A. Arber, Goethe’s Botany, Waltham, Massachusetts (1964).Google Scholar
  9. (24).
    P. Hume-Brown, The Life of Goethe, vol. 2, John Murray, London (1920), p. 441.Google Scholar
  10. (25).
    J.W. von Goethe, Einwirkung der neueren Philosophie; quoted in E. Cassirer, ibid. (1963).Google Scholar
  11. (30).
    L. Agassiz, The Structure of Animal Life, Scribner, New York (1866), p. 122.Google Scholar
  12. (31).
    See E. Perrier, La Philosophie Zoologique avant Darwin(ed. F. Alcan), Ballière, Paris (1884), preface, 10.Google Scholar
  13. (32).
    L. Oken, Lehrbuch der Naturphilosophie Berlin (1809–1811);Google Scholar
  14. A. Tulk, Elements of Physiophilosophy, (Ray Society, London 1847), p. 492.Google Scholar
  15. (33).
    E. Serres, Précis d’Anatomie Transcendente, Paris (1842), p. 91.Google Scholar
  16. (35).
    A. Weismann, The Evolution Theory, vol. 1 (trans. J.A. and M.R. Thomson), Edward Arnold, London (1904), p. 28.Google Scholar
  17. (36).
    T.H. Huxley, On the theory of the vertebrate skull, Proc. Roy. Soc., 9 (1858), 381–457;CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. (37).
    C. Darwin, The Origin of Species, John Murray, London (sixth edition, 1872), p. 260.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© C.U.M. Smith 1976

Authors and Affiliations

  • C. U. M. Smith
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of Biological SciencesUniversity of Aston in BirminghamUK

Personalised recommendations