Skip to main content

In What Sense Is Unemployment a Proper Object of Moral Concern?

  • Chapter
On Unemployment

Abstract

Few non-Marxists argue that there is or at least should be something like a right to be employed—that is, an independent individual right to some sort of meaningful job that is enforceable against either a particular private employer or the state, and I do not intend to spend any time discussing the Marxist posi- tion here, for two reasons. First, because such discussions are already plentiful elsewhere.1 And second, because I am going to start with the assumption that we have already decided, for whatever reason, that we will not seek to replace capi- talism with socialism—that is, we have already decided to opt for mostly private ownership of the means of production and a free-market economy moderated by the protections of political liberalism instead of a system of public ownership of the means of production and a centrally planned economy, with or without the protections of political liberalism, regardless of the effect on unemployment that this decision may or may not have. So while I believe that Marxism (and for that matter all other forms of what we commonly call socialism) does not provide an attractive answer to the problem of unemployment, all things considered, I shall not argue for that position here, although I shall use the work of some Marxist critics of capitalism as well as the work of a great many capitalist economists to help explore what capitalism and especially liberal capitalism really entails. Nevertheless, nothing I am going to say in this work requires anyone to abandon the view that some form of socialism offers an attractive solution to the problem of unemployment if that is the view they currently maintain.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See, e.g., Richard J. Arneson, “Meaningful Work and Socialism,” Ethics 97 (1987): 517–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. For more on the various practical problems associated with these proposals, see Malcolm Sawyer, “Employer of Last Resort: Could It Deliver Full Employment and Price Stability?” Journal of Economic Issues 37 (2003): 881–907.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. See, e.g., David Neumark, Brandon Wall, and Junfu Zhang, “Do Small Businesses Create More Jobs? New Evidence for the United States from the National Establishment Times Series,” The Review of Economics and Statistics 93 (2011): 16–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. David L. Birch, Job Creation in America: How Our Smallest Companies Put the Most People to Work (New York: Free Press, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  5. For a description and discussion of both fundamental theorems, see Joseph E. Stiglitz, “The Invisible Hand and Modern Welfare Economics,” National Bureau of Economic Research, Working Paper No. 3641 (March 1991), esp. pp. 2–4. See also Amartya Sen, “The Moral Standing of the Market,” Social Philosophy and Policy 2.2 (1985): 1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. The “full information” and “instantaneous adjustment” qualifiers are of course necessary, for otherwise unemployment could still arise in a perfectly competitive market. See, e.g., Axel Leijonhufved, “Effective Demand Failures,” The Swedish Journal of Economics 75 (1973): 27–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Liebow, “No Man Can Live with the Terrible Knowledge that He Is Not Needed.”. The same, of course, also applies to women who want a job but cannot get one. For similar expressions of the deep debilitating power of unemployment on the human psyche, see, e.g., A.C. Pigou, Unemployment (London: Williams and Norgate, 1913), pp. 32–34

    Google Scholar 

  8. The origination of the term “Homo Faber” is usually credited to Benjamin Franklin but the term was perhaps used most extensively by Hannah Arendt and Max Scheler. See, e.g., Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition: Second Edition (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1958).

    Google Scholar 

  9. See Lisa Herzog, Inventing the Market: Smith, Hegel and Political Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), esp. p. 74

    Book  Google Scholar 

  10. Sean Sayers, Marx and Alienation (London: Palgrave MacmĂĽlan, 2011)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  11. Bertell Oilman, Alienation: Marx’s Conception of Man in Capitalist Society (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971)

    Google Scholar 

  12. See Richard Florida, The Rise of the Creative Class, Revisited (New York: Basic Books, 2012 [2011]).

    Google Scholar 

  13. See G. W. F. Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), Sec. 41–70, pp. 73–102.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Jeremy Waldron, The Right to Private Property (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988), Ch. 10, esp. pp. 353

    Google Scholar 

  15. Stephen R. Munzer, A Theory of Property (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  16. Margaret Jane Radin, “Property and Personhood,” Stanford Law Review 34 (1982): 957–1015.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Robert Reiff, “Alienation and Dehumanization,” in Auto Work and Its Discontents, ed. B. J. Widdick (Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1976), pp. 45–51

    Google Scholar 

  18. See, e.g., Ernest J. Weinrib, “The Case for the Duty to Rescue,” Yale Law journal 90 (1980): 247–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. See Thomas Nagel, “The Problem of Global Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (2005): 113–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Among contemporary political philosophers, the person most associated with the idea of providing everyone some sort of basic income is Philippe Van Parijs. See Philippe Van Parijs, Real Freedom for All: What (if anything) Can justify Capitalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Prominent luck egalitarians would include Ronald Dworldn, G. A. Cohen, Thomas Nagel, Erik Rakowski, John Roemer, Richard Arneson, and Philippe Van Parijs, although each elaborates the content of luck egalitarianism in different ways. See Richard J. Arneson, “Luck Egalitarianism and Prioritarianism,” Ethics 110 (2000): 339–349

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. See Mark R. Reiff, “Proportionality, Winner-Take-All, and Distributive Justice,” Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 8 (2009): 5–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. See Hillel Steiner, An Essay on Rights (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994)

    Google Scholar 

  24. For further discussion of this point, see Mark R. Reiff, “The Attack on Liberalism,” in Law and Philosophy, ed. Michael Freeman and Ross Harrison (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), pp. 173–210

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  25. See generally Daniel Kahneman, Thinking, Fast and Slow (New York: Farrar, Strauss and Giroux, 2011), pp. 322–341

    Google Scholar 

  26. Haim Levy, The Capital Asset Pricing Model in the 21st Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), p. 326.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See Cass Sunstein, Laws of Fear: Beyond the Precautionary Principle (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  28. For an important argument that this is an and perhaps the obligation of a liberal capitalist society, see Ronald Dworkin, “Liberalism,” in Public and Private Morality, ed. Stuart Hampshire (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  29. Indeed, avoiding the leveling down objection is often offered by supporters of the difference principle as the reason why their view is superior to that of strict egalitari-anism. See Campbell Brown, “Giving up Levelling Down,” Economics and Philosophy 19 (2003): 111–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. Larry Temldn, “Equality, Priority, and the Levelling down Objection,” in The Ldeal of Equality, ed. Matthew Clayton and Andrew Williams (New York: Palgrave, 2000), pp. 126–161

    Google Scholar 

  31. Elizabeth Anderson, “What Is the Point of Equality?” Ethics 109 (1999): 287–337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. See, e.g., Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, “Loss Aversion in Riskless Choice,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 106 (1991): 1039–1061.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Actually, it was Joan Robinson who said this, although she attributed it to Keynes. See Joan Robinson, “Kalecld and Keynes,” in Contributions to Modern Economics (New York: Academic Press, 1978[1964]), pp. 53–60

    Google Scholar 

  34. Pavlina R. Tcherneva, “Reorienting Fiscal Policy: A Bottom-up Approach,” Journal of Post-Keynesian Economics 37 (2014): 43–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2015 Mark R. Reiff

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Reiff, M.R. (2015). In What Sense Is Unemployment a Proper Object of Moral Concern?. In: On Unemployment. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-55000-2_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics