Advertisement

Mathematical Progress As Increased Scope

  • Madeline Muntersbjorn
Chapter
  • 657 Downloads
Part of the Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science book series (LEUS, volume 5)

Abstract

Well-chosen languages contribute to problem-solving success in the history of mathematics. Innovations in notation may not constitute progress on their own for philosophers who reject formalism. Yet successful languages are important concomitants of progress insofar as they enable mathematicians to state claims more broadly and recognize obscure relationships between different branches of mathematics. Platonists recognize the importance of Poincare’s ’happy innovations of language’ as a means whereby ever more mathematical reality is revealed. However, the distinction between what mathematics is about and the formal means used to study mathematics can rarely be made precise outside of isolated historical contexts. Understanding mathematical progress as increased scope is thus an alternative to Platonism’s “mathematical progress as genuine discovery” and formalism’s “mathematical progress as clever invention.”

Keywords

mathematical progress scope notation 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Baron, Margaret. (1969). The Origins of the Infinitesimal Calculus. Dover.Google Scholar
  2. Boole, George. ([1854] 1958). An Investigation of the Laws of Thought. Dover.Google Scholar
  3. Frege, Gottlob. (1997). The Frege Reader, Michael Beaney, ed. & trans. Blackwell.Google Scholar
  4. Hardy, G. H. (1929). “Mathematical Proof,” Mind 38: 1-25.Google Scholar
  5. Lakatos, Imre. (1976). Proofs and Refutations. Cambridge.Google Scholar
  6. Langer, Susanne. (1953). An Introduction to Symbolic Logic. Dover.Google Scholar
  7. McLarty, Colin. (2000). “Voir-Dire in the Case of Mathematical Progress,” E. Grosholz & H. Breger, eds., The Growth of Mathematical Knowledge. Kluwer: 269-280.Google Scholar
  8. Muntersbjorn, Madeline. (2003). “Representational Innovation and Mathematical Ontology,” Synthese 134: 159-180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Shapiro, Stewart. (2000). Thinking About Mathematics. Oxford.Google Scholar
  10. Van Heijenoort, Jean. (1970). Frege and Gödel. Harvard.Google Scholar
  11. Whitehead, A. N. (1911). An Introduction to Mathematics. New York: Henry Holt & Co.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer 2007

Authors and Affiliations

  • Madeline Muntersbjorn
    • 1
  1. 1.University of ToledoUSA

Personalised recommendations