Advertisement

Habit

Chapter
  • 430 Downloads
Part of the International Archives of the History of Ideas / Archives internationales d’histoire des idées book series (ARCH, volume 191)

5. Concluding Remarks

The role of habit in Ferguson’s conception of spontaneous social order is four-fold: firstly, it serves as the ‘Maker’s’ temporal insurance policy by guaranteeing that any advances made in the past are enshrined in human behaviour to the point where they become reflexive; secondly, being essentially human products, habits permit the exercise of our ‘will and choice’, play a central role in our moral development and allow our emotions to play their proper role in the maintenance of social life; thirdly, habit solves the abstract problem of identifying the basis for political authority and fourthly, habits enhance communal bonds, permitting and encouraging us to live in the social condition intended for us by Nature. Partly because of the effects of habit, a society underpinned by passions is neither random nor precarious; rather, it is highly ordered, integrated and progressive. Ferguson’s sophisticated appreciation of this fact suggests that his aversion to radical social change was probably more scientific than ideological.

Keywords

Moral Sense Moral Personality Spontaneous Order Social Sanction Impartial Spectator 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 879.
    Ch. III, Sections ii, iii, iv, v, vi and vii of the Principles, I. William Lehmann provides a good exposition of Ferguson’s treatment of habit in Adam Ferguson, (pp. 52–53, 67–77) as does David Kettler in Social and Political Thought of Adam Ferguson. The present chapter owes something to both.Google Scholar
  2. 880.
    Charles Camic, ‘The Matter of Habit’, American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 91(5), March 1986, 1039–87, p. 1047. Aristotle, Aquinas, Duns Scotus and William Ockham are just some of them. O. Fuchs, The Psychology of Habit According to William Ockham, St. Bonaventure, N.Y.: The Franciscan Institute, 1952, pp. xiii–xvii.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. 881.
    Donald Pickens, ‘Scottish Common sense Philosophy and Folkways’, Journal of Thought, Vol. 22, 1987, pp. 39–44.Google Scholar
  4. 882.
    Christopher J. Berry, ‘Sociality and Socialisation’ in Alexander Broadie (ed.) The Scottish Enlightenment, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003, pp. 243–57.Google Scholar
  5. 883.
    Camic, ‘The Matter of Habit’, pp. 1047–8. Unlike Ferguson, Kant did not regard habit and custom in positive terms but stressed the need for the emancipation of individuals from habit through the exercise of autonomous rationality. Jeffrey Minson, ‘Men and Manners: Kantian Humanism, Rhetoric and the History of Ethics’, Economy and Society, Vol. 18 (1), February, 1989, pp. 191–220, pp. 202–6.Google Scholar
  6. 884.
    Such as, William James and Samuel Butler in the nineteenth century and in the early twentieth experimental psychologists like Knight Dunlap, the author of Habits. Their Making and Unmaking, New York: Liveright Publishing Corporation, 1939.Google Scholar
  7. 885.
    P.I., p. 208Google Scholar
  8. 886.
    P.I., p. 234.Google Scholar
  9. 887.
    P.I., p. 232.Google Scholar
  10. 888.
    P.I., p. 234.Google Scholar
  11. 889.
    ‘It alone is what keeps us all within the bounds of ordinance and saves the children of fortune from the envious uprisings of the poor. It alone prevents the hardest and most repulsive walks of life from being deserted by those brought up to tread therein. It keeps the fisherman and the deck-hand at sea through the winter; it holds the miner in his darkness, and nails the countryman to his log-cabin and his lonely farm through all the months of snow; it protects us from invasion by the natives of the desert and the frozen zone. It dooms us all to fight out the battle of life upon the lines of our nurture or our early choice, and to make the best of a pursuit that disagrees, because there is not other for which we are fitted, and it is too late to begin again. It keeps different social strata from mixing’. William James, The Principles of Psychology, in 3 Vols, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1981, Vol. 1, p. 125.Google Scholar
  12. 890.
    P.I., p. 208.Google Scholar
  13. 891.
    Camic, ‘The Matter of Habit’, p. 1046. See this article for a more detailed historical treatment of habit in sociology.Google Scholar
  14. 892.
    P.I., p. 234.Google Scholar
  15. 893.
    P.I., pp. 224–5.Google Scholar
  16. 894.
    Essay, p. 23.Google Scholar
  17. 895.
    P.I., pp. 211–12.Google Scholar
  18. 896.
    Hume, Treatise, 3. 3. 5. p. 422.Google Scholar
  19. 897.
    ‘Human nature nowhere exists in the abstract’. P.II., p. 419; Essay, pp. 9–10.Google Scholar
  20. 898.
    Lehmann, Adam Ferguson, pp. 68–9.Google Scholar
  21. 899.
    Susan Shott, ‘Society, Self and Mind in Moral Philosophy’, Journal of the History of Behavioural Sciences, Vol. 12, 1976, pp. 39–46, p. 39. Shott also asserts that ‘(c)oncepts nearly equivalent to Mead’s notions of “role-taking”, the “generalised other”, and the “I”-“me” relationship are employed by the Scottish Moralists in their discussions of social and moral conduct’. Susan Shott, ‘The Development of Sociological Theory in America; A Sociology of Knowledge Interpretation’, in Larry T. Reynolds and Janice M. Reynolds, (eds), The Sociology of Sociology, New York: McKay, 1970, p. 18. Symbolic interactionism developed in first few decades of the twentieth century. It focused upon the ways in which ‘meanings emerge through interaction’ and emphasised ‘the ways in which human beings are distinctly symbol manipulating animals’. G. Marshall, Oxford Dictionary of Sociology, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998, p. 657.Google Scholar
  22. 900.
    Essay, pp. 22–4.Google Scholar
  23. 901.
    Essay, p. 23.Google Scholar
  24. 902.
    P.I., pp. 209–10.Google Scholar
  25. 903.
    Essay, pp. 16–17Google Scholar
  26. 904.
    Institutes, p. 111.Google Scholar
  27. 905.
    P.I., p. 202.Google Scholar
  28. 906.
    Institutes, p. 111. My emphasis.Google Scholar
  29. 907.
    P.I., pp. 217–18.Google Scholar
  30. 908.
    P.I., p. 208.Google Scholar
  31. 909.
    P.I., p. 225.Google Scholar
  32. 910.
    Essay, p. 119–21; P.I., p.219. James Murphy captures Ferguson’s position in this way: ‘[W]e begin with natural potentialities, custom shapes these potentialities into habit, and through rational reflection we order our habits in light of our moral ideals’. James Bernard Murphy, ‘Nature, Custom and Stipulation in the Semiotic of John Poinset’, Semiotica, Vol. 82 (1–2), 1990, pp. 33–68, p. 44.Google Scholar
  33. 911.
    Reesor, The Old and Middle Stoa, p. 12.Google Scholar
  34. 912.
    P.I., p. 131.Google Scholar
  35. 913.
    Institutes, p. 218.Google Scholar
  36. 914.
    P.I., p. 125. Adam Smith’s ideas on the development of the social self are particularly well developed. Shott,’ society, Self and Mind’ p. 42.Google Scholar
  37. 915.
    Institutes, p. 90.Google Scholar
  38. 916.
    P.I., pp. 126–7.Google Scholar
  39. 917.
    P.II., p. 128. Such a view is originally Hutchesonian. Susan M. Purviance, ‘Intersubjectivity and Sociable Relations in the Philosophy of Francis Hutcheson’ in J. Dwyer, and R.B. Sher (eds), Sociability and Society in Eighteenth Century Scotland, Edinburgh: The Mercat Press, 1993, pp. 24–5.Google Scholar
  40. 918.
    Strasser, The Normative Structure of Sociology, p. 48.Google Scholar
  41. 919.
    Essay, p. 36.Google Scholar
  42. 920.
    See ‘Principle of Moral Estimation’, No. 25, Collection of Essays, passim.Google Scholar
  43. 921.
    Institutes, p.168Google Scholar
  44. 922.
    ‘Of the Distinctions on Which we Act in Human Life’, Collection of Essays, No. 18, pp. 164–5.Google Scholar
  45. 923.
    Smith, Adam Ferguson, p. 40.Google Scholar
  46. 924.
    Essay, pp. 22–3. Hume makes the identical argument in the Treatise: ‘In a little time, custom and habit operating on the tender minds of the children, makes them sensible of the advantages, which they may reap from society’. 3. 2. 2. p. 486.Google Scholar
  47. 925.
    P.I., p. 215. John Millar later wrote that class distinctions were perpetuated and maintained via habit. Millar, An Historical View of the English Government, pp. 290–2.Google Scholar
  48. 926.
    Kettler, Social and Political Thought of Adam Ferguson, p. 195.Google Scholar
  49. 927.
    P.I., p. 218.Google Scholar
  50. 928.
    Thoits, ’sociology of Emotion’, p. 337.Google Scholar
  51. 929.
    P.II., p. 142.Google Scholar
  52. 930.
    Institutes, p. 162.Google Scholar
  53. 931.
    P.I., p. 322.Google Scholar
  54. 932.
    Essay, p. 16. Montesquieu also accounted for the existence of cultural universals in terms of ‘natural laws’. Laws, 1. 1. 1., p. 1. See also Persian Letters, Translated with an Introduction and Notes by C.J. Betts, London: Penguin, 1973.Google Scholar
  55. 933.
    P.II., p. 270. Neither does the ‘consent of ancestors, with whom a practice originated, bind their posterity’. P.II., p. 234.Google Scholar
  56. 934.
    P.II., p. 290. See also P.II., p. 245.Google Scholar
  57. 935.
    Hume, Treatise, 2. 2. 10. p. 556.Google Scholar
  58. 936.
    P.II., p. 234.Google Scholar
  59. 937.
    William Lehmann was the first to detect this proto-psychology in Ferguson’s writings. Lehmann, Adam Ferguson, pp. 69–71.Google Scholar
  60. 938.
    P.I., pp. 137–44.Google Scholar
  61. 939.
    P.I., p. 133.Google Scholar
  62. 940.
    P.I., p. 21.Google Scholar
  63. 941.
    P.I., p. 234.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer 2006

Personalised recommendations