Advertisement

A Partial Look at Trope Theory

  • Bo R. Meinertsen
Chapter
Part of the Philosophical Studies Series book series (PSSP, volume 136)

Abstract

Trope theory (‘moderate nominalism’, ‘trope nominalism’) is usually introduced as the view that properties are not universal (repeatable) but particular (or ‘particularized’). The particular size, shape, weight, colour, etc. of this mug standing on my desk are examples of such particular properties.

References

  1. Armstrong, D. M. (1989a). A combinatorial theory of possibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Armstrong, D. M. (1989b). Universals: An opinionated introduction. Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press.Google Scholar
  3. Armstrong, D. M. (1997). A world of states of affairs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Campbell, K. (1981). The metaphysics of abstract particulars. In A. French, T. E. Uehling, & H. K. Wettstein (Eds.), Midwest studies in philosophy: The foundations of analytic philosophy (Vol. 6, pp. 477–488). Minneapolis, Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  5. Campbell, K. (1990). Abstract particulars. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  6. Campbell, K. (1999). The place of relations in a trope philosophy. Unpublished ms.Google Scholar
  7. Daly, C. (1994). Tropes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 94, 140–59.Google Scholar
  8. Denkel, A. (1997). On the compresence of tropes. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 72, 599–606.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Dodd, J. (1999). Farewell to states of affairs. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 77, 146–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Ehring, D. (2011). Tropes: Properties, objects, and mental causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Hochberg, H. (1995). Abstracts functions, existence and relations in the Russell-Meinong dispute, the Bradley paradox and the realism-nominalism controversy. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 50, 273–291.Google Scholar
  12. Loux, M. J. (1998). Metaphysics: A contemporary introduction. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Martin, C. B. (1980). Substance substantiated. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 58, 3–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Maurin, A.-S. (2002). If tropes. Dordrect: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Mertz, D. W. (1996). Moderate realism and its logic. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Moreland, J. P. (2001). Universals. Chesham: Acumen.Google Scholar
  17. Mulligan, K., Simons, P., & Smith, B. (1984). Truthmakers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 44, 287–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Persson, J. (1997). Causal facts. Lund: Library of Theoria.Google Scholar
  19. Rosenkrantz, G. S. (1993). Haecceity: An ontological essay. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Russell, B. (1948). Human knowledge: Its scope and limits. New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
  21. Simons, P. (1994). Particulars in particular clothing: Three trope theories of substance. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54, 553–575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Simons, P. (2010). Relations and truthmaking. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 84, 199–213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Stout, G. F. (1921). The nature of universals and propositions. (Reprinted in Studies in philosophy and psychology, pp. 123–135, by G. F. Stout Ed., 1930, London: Macmillan).Google Scholar
  24. Stout, G. F. (1923). Are the characteristics of particular things universal or particular? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, (suppl.), 3, 114–122.Google Scholar
  25. Williams, D. C. (1953). The elements of being. Review of Metaphysics, 7, 3–18, 171–92.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  • Bo R. Meinertsen
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyTongji UniversityShanghaiChina

Personalised recommendations