Advertisement

Sensitive Perception, Stable Disposition and Deliberation: Starting from “Virtue Is Knowledge”

  • Cheng Yuan
Chapter

Abstract

Moral deliberation is usually characterized as one kind of mental process which provides us convincing reason to make morally right choice by clear reasoning, forming judgments, or explicit self-reflection guided by moral principles. However, this kind of understanding renders an intellectualist illusion: one can acquire moral quality only by reasoning skillfully. In this chapter, by re-reading Socrates’ thesis and following suggestions of philosophers such as B. Williams and John McDowell, the author explores the intrinsic connection between deliberation with perception, as well as connection between deliberation with disposition: one can make deliberations morally, which can be regarded as the natural result produced and released by the person who has been already morally cultivated and therefore is equipped with such moral perception. Similarly, a good performance of deliberation tightly relies on or even is rooted in a well-formed disposition which prevents deliberator from being distracted by disturbing “deliberation.”

References

  1. Achtenberg, Deborah. 2002. Cognition of Value in Aristotle’s Ethics: Promise of Enrichment, Threat of Destruction. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
  2. Aristotle. 2009. The Nicomachean Ethics(Oxford Worlds Classics), translated by W. D. Ross. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Audi, Robert. 1995. The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. New York City: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  4. ———. 2013. Moral Perception. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Blum, Lawrence. 1994. Moral Perception and Particularity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Deigh, John. 1995. Ethics. In The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, edited by Robert Audi. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Dewey, John. 1996. Theory of the moral life. New York: Irvington Publishers.Google Scholar
  8. Dewey, John and Tufts, James Hayden, 1908. Ethics, New York: Henry Holt.Google Scholar
  9. Dreyfus, Hubert L. and Dreyfus, Stuart E. 1991. “Towards A Phenomenology of Ethical Expertise.” Human Studies 14 (4):229–250. See also: 1992. “What is Moral Maturity? Towards A Phenomenology of Ethical Expertise. “In Revisioning Philosophy, edited by James Ogilvy,111–131. Albany: State University of New York.Google Scholar
  10. Kinsella, Elizabeth A. and Pitman, Allan. 2012. Phronesis As Professional Knowledge: Practical Wisdom in the Professions. London: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1989. “Ethos und Logos”. in Anados: Festschrift für Helmut Kuhn, editedy by Hofmann Rupert. Weinheim: VCH, Acta Humaniora.Google Scholar
  12. ––––—. 1991. “Die Idee des Guten zwischen Plato und Aristoteles” and “Die sokratische Frage und Aristoteles.” in Gesammelte Werke Band 7: Griechische Philosophie III. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr Verlag.Google Scholar
  13. ———. 1993. “Begriffsgeschichte als Philosophie” in Gesammelte Werke Band 2: Hermeneutik II: Wahrheit und Methode - Ergänzungen, Register. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr Verlag.Google Scholar
  14. Hegel, Georg W. F. 1986. Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie (Werke Band 12), edited by Eva Moldenhauer and Karl Markus Michel, Suhrkamp Verlag.Google Scholar
  15. Heidegger, Martin. 2009. Basic Concepts of Aristotelian Philosophy, translated by Robert D. Metcalf and Mark B. Tanzer, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Published in German: Heidegger, Martin. 2002. Gesamtausgabe, 18: Grundbegriffe der aristotelischen Philosophie, edited by Mark Michalski, Frankfurt am Main: Vittorio Klostermann.Google Scholar
  16. Honneth, Axel. 2002. “Between Hermeneutics and Hegelianism: John McDowell and The Challenge of Moral Realism.” In Reading McDowell, edited by Nicholas H. Smith. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  17. James, William. 1922. Pragmatism, a New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking: Popular Lectures on Philosophy. New York&London: Longmans, Green and Co.Google Scholar
  18. Mandelbaum, Maurice. 1955. The Phenomenology of Moral Experience. Glencoe: The Free Press.Google Scholar
  19. McDowell, John H. 1979. “Virtue and Reason.” Monist 62 (3):331–350CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. ––––––. 2009. The Engaged Intellect: Philosophical Essays. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  21. ––––––.1996. Mind and World. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Piaget, Jean. 1948. The Moral Judgment of the Child, translated by Marjory Gabain. Glencoe, Illinois: The Free Press.Google Scholar
  23. Scott, Dominic. 2006. Plato’s Meno. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Simon, Yves R. M. 1986. The Definition of Moral Virtue, edited by Vukan Kuic. New York: Fordham University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Tiberius, Valerie. 2002. “Virtue and practical deliberation.” Philosophical Studies 111(2): 147–172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Tang, Refeng 唐熱風. 2005. “Virtue and Practical Wisdom in Aristotle’s Ethics.” Philosophical Research 5: 70–79Google Scholar
  27. Wang, Huaping 王華平. 2015. “Intention and Intentional Action.” Journal of Dialectics of Nature 37(2): 1–8Google Scholar
  28. Williams, Bernard. 2006 [1985]. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. ———. 2008. Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline. Princeton & Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  30. ––––––. 2008. “Acting as the Virtuous Person Acts.” In The Sense of The Past : Essays in The History of Philosophy, pp.189–197. Princeton & Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  31. ––––––. 1993. Shame and Necessity. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd. 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  • Cheng Yuan
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyCapital Normal UniversityBeijingChina

Personalised recommendations