Advertisement

Whatever Happened to Swinging and Rolling: Faint Echoes and a Late Insight

  • Jochen Büttner
Chapter
Part of the Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science book series (BSPS, volume 335)

Abstract

Confronted with overwhelming problems, in or shortly after 1602, Galileo abandoned his ardent investigation into the relation of swinging and rolling without, however, entirely giving up on his approach. The fundamental idea of his early research, namely, to approximate motion along an arc by motion along polygonal paths made up of a series of inclined planes, still resonates in the Discorsi, albeit in but one argument. By means of this argument, Galileo intended to demonstrate that the brachistochrone, i.e., the curve between two points along which motion is completed in least time, was an upright arc. It is argued that this was a late attempt by Galileo to make his earlier considerations regarding swinging and rolling bear fruit and that he had reason to surmise that his argument was flawed. The chapter, moreover, discusses how, stimulated by his perusal of Giovanni Battista Baliani’s De motu naturali gravium solidorum published in 1638, Galileo briefly resumed his work on swinging and rolling. Based on the understanding he himself had gained in his own earlier investigation into the same problem, Galileo drafted a critique of Baliani’s approach as part of which, for the first time, he devised a proof of the law of the pendulum. Galileo had thus accomplished in part what he had sought to achieve some 35 years earlier, and the new proof was indeed earmarked for inclusion in a second edition of the Discorsi.

References

  1. Ariotti, P.E. (1971/1972) Aspects of the conception and development of the pendulum in the 17th century. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 8, 329–410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Baliani, G.B. (1638). De motu naturali gravium solidorum Joannis Baptistae Baliani. Genuae: Farroni.Google Scholar
  3. Baliani, G.B., & Baroncelli, G. (1998). De motu naturali gravium solidorum et liquidorum. (Biblioteca della scienza italiana, Vol. 19). Firenze: Giunti.Google Scholar
  4. Büttner, J., Damerow, P., & Renn, J. (2004). Galileo’s unpublished treatises. In C.R. Palmerino & J.M.M.H. Thijssen (Eds.), The reception of the Galilean science of motion in seventeenth-century Europe (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 239, pp. 99–117). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  5. Capecchi, D. (2014). The problem of the motion of bodies. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Caverni, R. (1972). Storia del metodo sperimentale in Italia. New York: Johnson Reprint.Google Scholar
  7. Damerow, P., & Renn, J. (2012). The equilibrium controversy: Guidobaldo del Monte’s critical notes on the mechanics of Jordanus and Benedetti and their historical and conceptual backgrounds, Vol. 2, Ed. Open Access). Berlin: Max Planck research library for the history and development of knowledge sources.Google Scholar
  8. Damerow, P., Renn, J., & Rieger, S. (2001). Hunting the white elephant: When and how did Galileo discover the law of fall? In J. Renn (Ed.), Galileo in context (pp. 29–150). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Dijksterhuis, E.J., & Maier-Leibnitz, H. (2002). Die Mechanisierung des Weltbildes (2nd ed.). Berlin: SpringerGoogle Scholar
  10. Erlichson, H. (1998). Galileo’s work on swiftest descent from a circle and how he almost proved the circle itself was the minimum time path. The American Mathematical Monthly, 105(4), 338–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fuhrer, T. (1993). Der Begriff veri simile bei Cicero und Augustin. Museum Helveticum, 50(2), 107–125.Google Scholar
  12. Galilei, G., & Giusti, E. (Eds.) (1990). Discorsi e dimostrazioni matematiche intorno a due nuove scienze attinenti alla mecanica ed i movimenti locali (1990th ed.). Torino: Einaudi.Google Scholar
  13. Galilei, G., Crew, H., & Salvio, A.D. (1954). Dialogues concerning two new sciences, New York: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
  14. Goldstine, H.H. (1980). A history of the calculus of variations from the 17th through the 19th century. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Istituto della Enciclopedia Italiana (Roma). (1963). Dizionario biografico degli Italiani, (bacca-baratta, Vol. 5). Istituto della Enciclopedia Italiana, RomeGoogle Scholar
  16. Moscovici, S. (1967). L’Expérience du mouvement: Jean-Baptiste Baliani, disciple et critique de Galilée, Collection Histoire de la pensée (Vol 16). Paris: Hermann.Google Scholar
  17. Palmieri P (2009). A phenomenology of Galileo’s experiments with pendulums. The British Journal for the History of Science, 42(4), 479–513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Raphael, R.J. (2012). Printing Galileo’s Discorsi: A collaborative affair. Annals of Science, 69(4):483–513.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Settle, T. (1966). Galilean science: Essays in the mechanics and dynamics of the Discorsi. Ph.D. thesis, Cornell University.Google Scholar
  20. Westfall, R.S. (1989). Floods along the Bisenzio: Science and technology in the age of Galileo. Technology and Culture, 30(4), 879–907.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Wisan, W.L. (1974). The new science of motion: A study of Galileo’s De motu locali. Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 13, 103–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Wisan, W.L. (1984). Galileo and the process of scientific creation. ISIS, 75(2), 269–286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  • Jochen Büttner
    • 1
  1. 1.Max Planck Institute for the History of ScienceBerlinGermany

Personalised recommendations