Advertisement

Some Misunderstandings About the Moral Significance of Technology

  • Peter-Paul VerbeekEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Philosophy of Engineering and Technology book series (POET, volume 17)

Abstract

The discussion about moral agency and technology is troubled by some severe misunderstandings. Too often, the claim that technologies are involved in moral agency is misread for the claim that technologies are moral agents themselves. Much of the discussion then focuses on the question whether not only humans but also technologies can have intentionality, freedom, responsibility, and, ultimately, moral agency. From the perspective of mediation theory, this discussion remains caught in a dualist paradigm that locates human beings and technological artifacts in two separate realms, humans being intentional and free, technologies being instrumental and mute. Against the question to what extent technologies can be moral agents, mediation theory makes it possible to investigate how intentionality, freedom, and agency are in fact the result of intricate connections and interactions between human beings and technological artifacts. Rather than checking if technologies can meet a pre-given criterion of moral agency, we need to re-conceptualize the phenomenon of moral agency itself in order to understand the roles of technologies in our daily lives.

Keywords

Deep Brain Stimulation Moral Agency Moral Action Moral Decision Unborn Child 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Berlin, I. (1979). Two concepts of liberty. In Four essays on liberty (pp. 118–172). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Foucault, M. (1997). What is enlightenment? In P. Rabinow (Ed.), M. Foucault, ethics: Subjectivity and truth. New York: New Press.Google Scholar
  3. Freud, S. (1955). A difficulty in the path of psycho-analysis. In J. Strachey (Ed. & Trans.), The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 17). London: Hogarth Press.Google Scholar
  4. Ihde, D. (1990). Technology and the lifeworld. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Knight, W. (2005, February 5). Mirror that reflects your future self. New Scientist, (2485), 23.Google Scholar
  6. Latour, B. (1993). We have never been modern (C. Porter, Trans.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. (Translation of: Nous n’avons jamais été modernes, Paris: La Découverte, 1991).Google Scholar
  7. Leentjens, et al. (2004). Manipuleerbare wilsbekwaamheid: Een ethisch probleem bij elektrostimulatie van de nucleus subthalamicus voor ernstige ziekte van Parkinson. Nederlands Tijdschrift voor Geneeskunde, 148, 1394–1398.Google Scholar
  8. Peterson, M. (2012). Three objections to Verbeek. In E. Selinger et al. (Ed.), Book symposium on Peter Paul Verbeek’s moralizing technology: Understanding and designing the morality of things, philosophy and technology (Vol. 25, pp. 619–625).Google Scholar
  9. Verbeek, P. P. (2005). What things do: Philosophical reflections on technology, agency, and design. University Park: Penn State University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Verbeek, P. P. (2011). Moralizing technology: Understanding and designing the morality of things. Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Verbeek, P. P. (2012). The irony of humanism: On the complexities of discussing the moral significance of things. In E. Selinger et al. (Ed.), Book symposium on Peter Paul Verbeek’s moralizing technology: Understanding and designing the morality of things, philosophy and technology (Vol. 25, pp. 626–631).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of TwenteEnschedeThe Netherlands

Personalised recommendations