Skip to main content

Towards a Post-human Intra-actional Account of Sociomaterial Agency (and Morality)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Philosophy of Engineering and Technology ((POET,volume 17))

Abstract

In the history of ethical thought there has always been an intimate relationship between agency and questions of morality. But what does this mean for artefacts? It would not be too controversial to claim that the idea that artefacts have, or embody, some level of agency—even if it is very limited or derived in some way—has become generally accepted. However, there still seems to be wide disagreements as to what is meant by the agency of artefacts, how it is accounted for, and the subsequent moral implications of such agency. I will suggest that one’s account of the agency of artefacts is fundamental to the subsequent discussion of the moral status and implications of artefacts, or technology more generally. In this contribution I will outline two different accounts of sociomaterial agency: (a) a human-centred inter-actional account (Johnson and VSD) and (b) a post-human intra-actional account (drawing on Latour, Barad and Heidegger). I will show that the post-human intra-actional account of sociomaterial agency posits the social and technical as ontologically inseparable from the start. Such a position has important implications for how one might understand sociomaterial agency and how one might deal with it. I will propose that the authors in the post-human approach all share what I call a ‘co-constitutive’ account of agency in which agency is not an attribute of the human or the technical as such but rather the outcome of intra-action. I will endeavour to illustrate the implications of such an account for our understanding of sociomaterial agency by considering the phenomenon of plagiarism detection. I will conclude by proposing disclosive ethics (in particular disclosive archaeology) as a possible way forward in dealing with the ethical and political implications of post-human intra-agencies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Philosophers of action in the analytical tradition have asserted that an action, in some basic sense, is something an agent does that is ‘intentional under some description’ (Donald Davidson 1980). They argue that there is a conceptual tie between genuine action, on the one hand, and intention, on the other. However tracking down the link between intention and action is not a simple matter at all—the large amount of work in action philosophy is testimony to this fact. In the continental tradition, especially in the work of Michel Foucault (1977) the original (or originating) subject is taken as deeply problematic. For Foucault subjects are the outcomes of discursive formations (constituted through prevailing power/knowledge regimes). Each regime of power/knowledge sustains a different type of subjectivity (i.e. the religious subject, the academic subject, the business subject, and so forth). If the original subject does not exist does it mean that particular ‘subject centred’ notion of agency does not make sense? Foucault would suggest not. To reject the autonomy (of the original subject) is not to reject agency. What is disputed is the necessary connection with an originating intention. Actions are intentional (under some description) but the intentionality does not originate in the subject and it transcends the subject in it being exercised. According to him there is often nobody (no specific actor) there to have ‘invented’ it as such (Foucault 1977). In social theory the relation between social structure and human agency has been a central and enduring problem as exemplified in the work of, for example, Anthony Giddens (1984).

  2. 2.

    Central to Heidegger’s ideas is his notion of the ‘ontological difference’. The ontological difference is the difference between being and entities. What an entity is depends on meaning-conditions that make entities stand out as that which it is. These conditions make up the being of entities. As Heidegger suggests “the being of entities ‘is’ not itself an entity” (Heidegger 1927/1962, p. 6); the being of entities is rather the implied conditions of possibilities (or horizon) against which entities make sense at all. Thus, the being of technology is not itself an artefact or system but rather the condition of possibilities against which artefacts emerge as meaningful. As such the being of technology reveals or discloses worlds.

  3. 3.

    It is therefore no surprise that for Heidegger the essence of modern technology is the way of being of modern humans—a way of conducting themselves towards the world—that sees the world as something to be ordered and shaped in line with our projects, intentions and desires—a ‘will to power’ that manifest itself a “will to technology”. It is in this technological mood that problems show up as requiring technical solutions. The term ‘mood’ here is used in a collective sense, like the ‘mood of the meeting’ or the ‘mood of our times’. He calls this technological mood ‘enframing’ (Gestell in German). For us, in the technological age the world is already ‘framed’ as a world available ‘to be made’, ‘to be shaped’ for our ongoing possibilities to express our existence, to be whatever we are, as business men, engineers, consultants, academics, teenagers, etc. In short: the need for modern technology makes sense because we already live in the technological age or mood where the world (and us as beings that are never ‘out’ of the world) are already framed in this way—as available resources for the ongoing challenging and ordering of the world by us, which is for him the essence of the ‘modern’ mood.

  4. 4.

    Here I am using Rouse’s (2007) normative conception of practice.

  5. 5.

    Here I follow Foucault (1972, 1994) and his notion of discourse and discursive formations.

  6. 6.

    The relationship between originality, authorship and ownership is a complex cultural and legal history of the rise of intellectual property rights which cannot be covered here (see Hesse 2002; Bracha 2006).

  7. 7.

    Detection here is defined as being outside of the ‘green’ zone in the originality report, i.e. having a correspondence of greater that 24 % with the texts in the Turnitin database. This percentage was determined by Turnitin themselves to compensate for incidental matches or false positives (which one would expect in a nine billion document database) and legitimate quotations.

  8. 8.

    A more technical definition of hash function is “A hash function is a function that converts an input from a (typically) large domain [input values] into an output in a (typically) smaller range (the hash value, often a subset of the integers) (from http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hash_function).

  9. 9.

    Refer to Schleimer et al. (2003) for a more detailed discussion.

  10. 10.

    Blue: less than 20 matching words; Green: 0–24 % matching text; Yellow: 25–49 % matching text; Orange: 50–74 % matching text; Red: 75–100 % matching text.

References

  • Achterhuis, H. (1995). De moralisering van de apparaten. Socialisme en Democratie, 52(1), 3–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barad, K. (1996). Meeting the universe halfway: Realism and social constructivism without contradiction. In L. Nelson & J. Nelson (Eds.), Feminism, science, and the philosophy of science (pp. 161–194). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barad, K. (2003). Posthumanist performativity: Toward an understanding of how matter comes to matter. Signs, 28(3), 801–831.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borgman, A. (1984). Technology and the character of contemporary life. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bracha, O. (2006). The ideology of authorship revisited. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=869446. Accessed April 2007.

  • Brey, P. (1999). The ethics of representation and action in virtual reality. Ethics and Information Technology, 1(1), 5–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brey, P. (2004). Ethical aspects of face recognition systems in public places. Journal of Information Communication and Ethics in Society, 2(2), 97–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (1993). Bodies that matter: On the discursive limits of “sex”. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, M., Howe, D., & Nissenbaum, H. (2008). Values in design: Theory and practice. In J. van den Hoven & J. Weckert (Eds.), Moral philosophy and information technology (pp. 322–353). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1972). The archaeology of knowledge and the discourse on language (A. M. Sheridan Smith, Trans.). New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1977). What is an author? (D. F. Bouchard & S. Simon, Trans.). In Language, counter-memory, practice (pp. 124–127). Ithaca/New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1994). The order of things: An archaeology of the human sciences. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B., & Nissenbaum, H. (1996). Bias in computer systems. ACM Transactions on Information Systems, 14(3), 330–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, B., Kahn, P. H., Jr., & Borning, A. (2006). Value sensitive design and information systems. In P. Zhang & D. Galletta (Eds.), Human-computer interaction in management information systems: Foundations (pp. 348–372). Armonk/London: M.E. Sharpe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giddens, A. (1984). The constitution of society. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heather, J. (2010). Turnitoff: Identifying and fixing a hole in current plagiarism detection software. Assessment & Evaluation in Higher Education, 35(6), 647–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1927/1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1971). Poetry, language and thought. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1977). The question concerning technology and other essays. New York: Harper Torchbooks.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, M. (1999). Electric language. New York: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, C. (2002). The rise of intellectual property, 700 B.C.—A.D. 2000: An idea in the balance. Daedalus, 131(2), 26–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, R. M. (1993). A plagiarism pentimento. Journal of Teaching Writing, 11(2), 233–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, R. M. (1995). Plagiarisms, authorships, and the academic death penalty. College English, 57(1), 788–805.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. (1991). Instrumental realism: The interface between philosophy of science and philosophy of technology. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Introna, L. D. (2007). Maintaining the reversibility of foldings: Making the ethics (politics) of information technology visible. Ethics and Information Technology, 9(1), 11–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Introna, L. D. (2009). Ethics and the speaking of things. Theory Culture and Society, 26(4), 398–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Introna, L. D., & Nissenbaum, H. (2000). The internet as a democratic medium: Why the politics of search engines matters. The Information Society, 16(3), 169–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Introna, L. D., & Whittaker, L. (2006). Power, cash and convenience: Translations in the political site of the ATM. The Information Society, 22(5), 325–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Introna, L. D., & Wood, D. (2004). Picturing algorithmic surveillance: The politics of facial recognition systems. Surveillance and Society, 2(2/3), 177–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, D. (2006). Computer systems: Moral entities but not moral agents. Ethics and Information Technology, 8(4), 195–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lathrop, A. (2000). Student cheating and plagiarism in the internet era: A wake-up call. Englewood: Libraries Unlimited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1991). Technology is society made durable. In J. Law (Ed.), A sociology of monsters: Essays on power, technology and domination (pp. 103–131). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1999). Pandora’s hope. Essays on the reality of science studies. Cambridge, MA/London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2002). Morality and technology: The end of the means. Theory Culture and Society, 19(5 & 6), 247–260.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2003). The promise of constructivism. In D. Ihde & E. Selinger (Eds.), Chasing technoscience: Matrix for materiality (pp. 27–46). Bloomington/Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2005). Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network-theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leki, I., & Carson, J. (1997). Completely different worlds: EAP and the writing experiences of ESL students in university courses. TESOL Quarterly, 31(1), 39–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lynch, J. (2002). The perfectly acceptable practice of literary theft: Plagiarism, copyright, and the eighteenth century. Colonial Williamsburg: The Journal of the Colonial Williamsburg Foundation, 24(4), 51–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman, D. A. (1988). The design of everyday things. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pecorari, D. (2003). Good and original: Plagiarism and patchwriting in academic second-language writing. Journal of Second Language Writing, 12(4), 317–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roig, M. (2001). Plagiarism and paraphrasing criteria of college and university professors. Ethics and Behavior, 11(3), 307–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (2004). Barad’s feminist naturalism. Hypatia, 19(1), 142–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (2007). Social practices and normativity. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 37(1), 46–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saltmarsh, S. (2004). Graduating tactics: Theorizing plagiarism as consumptive practice. Journal of Further and Higher Education, 28(4), 445–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saltmarsh, S. (2005). ‘White pages’ in the academy: Plagiarism, consumption and racist rationalities. International Journal of Educational Integrity, 1(1). http://www.ojs.unisa.edu.au/journals/index.php/IJEI/article/viewFile/17/65

  • Schleimer, S., Wilkerson, D., & Aiken, A. (2003, June). Winnowing: Local algorithms for document fingerprinting. In Proceedings of the ACM SIGMOD international conference on management of data (pp. 76–85).

    Google Scholar 

  • Shi, L. (2004). Textual borrowing in second-language writing. Written Communication, 21(2), 171–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek, P. P. (2005). What things do – Philosophical reflections on technology, agency, and design. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek, P. P. (2006). Materializing morality – Design ethics and technological mediation. Science Technology and Human Values, 31(3), 361–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vojak, C. (2006). What market culture teaches students about ethical behaviour. Ethics and Education, 1(2), 177–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winner, L. (1980). Do artefacts have politics. Daedalus, 109, 121–136.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lucas D. Introna .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Introna, L.D. (2014). Towards a Post-human Intra-actional Account of Sociomaterial Agency (and Morality). In: Kroes, P., Verbeek, PP. (eds) The Moral Status of Technical Artefacts. Philosophy of Engineering and Technology, vol 17. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7914-3_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics