Entangled Life pp 105-126 | Cite as

Adaptation, Adaptation to, and Interactive Causes

Chapter
Part of the History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences book series (HPTL, volume 4)

Abstract

This paper develops alternative ways of understanding ‘adaptation to’ specific environmental conditions, with particular attention to the explanatory power offered by differing conceptions, the concomitant epistemic demands they make of explanations, and the models such explanations employ. It is shown that explanations of adaptation to particular environmental conditions can satisfy important intuitions only if the environmental conditions to which phenotypes are adapted are interactive causes of fitness. However, taking this constraint to be both necessary and sufficient for ‘adaptation to’ imposes epistemic burdens on our explanatory practice, and risks violating yet other intuitions. The paper briefly explores the consequences of the constraint for the idea that selection requires shared environments, the idea that selection requires a homogeneous environment, the idea that phenotypes may be extended, and the idea that niches may be constructed.

Keywords

Reproductive Success Relative Fitness Causal Condition Causal Influence Selection Gradient 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Brandon, Robert N. 1990. Adaptation and environment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Brandon, Robert N., and Janis Antonovics. 1996. The coevolution of organism and environment. In Concepts and methods in evolutionary biology, ed. Robert N. Brandon, 161–178. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Caswell, Hal. 2001. Matrix population models. Sunderland: Sinauer.Google Scholar
  4. Dawkins, Richard. 1999. The extended phenotype. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Eldredge, Niles. 1986. Information, economics, and evolution. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 17: 351–369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Glymour, Bruce. 1998. Contrastive, non-probabilistic statistical explanations. Philosophy of Science 65: 448–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Glymour, Bruce. 2007. In defense of explanatory deductivism. In Causation and explanation, ed. Joseph Campbell, Michael O’Rourke, and Harry Silverstein, 133–154. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  8. Glymour, Bruce. 2011. Modeling environments: Interactive causation and adaptation to environmental conditions. Philosophy of Science 78: 448–471.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Grant, Peter R. 1991. Natural selection and Darwin’s finches. Scientific American 265: 82–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Guisan, Antione, and Wilfried Thuiller. 2005. Predicting species distribution: Offering more than simple habitat models. Ecology Letters 8: 993–1009.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Heywood, James. 2010. Explaining patterns in modern ruminant diversity: Contingency or constraint? Biological Journal of the Linnean Society 99: 657–672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Hunt, Kevin D. 1994. The evolution of human bipedality: Ecology and functional morphology. Journal of Human Evolution 23: 183–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Jaenike, John. 1978. An hypothesis to account for the maintenance of sex within populations. Evolutionary Theory 3: 191–194.Google Scholar
  14. Johnson, Matthew D. 2007. Measuring habitat quality: A review. The Condor 109: 489–504.Google Scholar
  15. Kerr, Benjamin, and Peter Godfrey-Smith. 2002. Individualist and multi-level perspectives on selection in structured populations. Biology and Philosophy 17: 477–517.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Lande, Russell, and Stevan J. Arnold. 1983. The measurement of selection on correlated characters. Evolution 37: 1210–1226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Lennox, James G., and Bradley E. Wilson. 1994. Natural selection and the struggle for existence. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 25: 65–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Levene, Howard. 1953. Genetic equilibrium when more than one ecological niche is available. American Naturalist 87: 331–333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Levin, Donald. 1975. Pest pressure and recombination systems in plants. American Naturalist 109: 437–451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Lewontin, Richard C. 1970. The units of selection. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 1: 1–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Maynard Smith, John. 1976. What determines the rate of evolution? American Naturalist 110: 331–338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. McFadden, Bruce. 1992. Fossil horses. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Odling-Smee, F. John, Kevin N. Laland, and Marcus W. Feldman. 2003. Niche construction: The neglected process in evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Pearl, Judea. 2000. Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Roughgarden, Jonathan. 1979. Theory of population genetics and evolutionary ecology. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  26. Schluter, Dolph. 1988. Estimating the form of natural selection on a quantitative trait. Evolution 42: 849–861.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Spirtes, Peter, Clark Glymour, and Richard Scheines. 2000. Causation, prediction, and search, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  28. Toju, Hirokazu, and Teiji Sota. 2006. Imbalance of predator and prey armament: Geographic clines in phenotypic interface and natural selection. American Naturalist 167: 105–117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. van Fraassen, Bas. 1980. The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Wheeler, Peter E. 1991. The influence of bipedalism on the energy and water budgets of early hominids. Journal of Human Evolution 21: 117–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyKansas State UniversityManhattanUSA

Personalised recommendations