Advertisement

Evolutionary Theory and the Epistemology of Science

  • Kevin McCain
  • Brad Weslake
Chapter
Part of the History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences book series (HPTL, volume 1)

Abstract

The sciences offer us a detailed picture of the world in which we live. But why is it rational to accept this picture? Evolutionary theory provides a beautiful case study of the way in which scientific theories are supported by their evidence. In this chapter we provide a guide for teachers who wish to use evolutionary theory to explain the way in which scientific theories are supported, and to explain what is required for a theory to be rationally accepted. Our method is to consider evolutionary theory in the light of a range of criticisms that have been made by its critics: that it is a theory rather than a fact, that it cannot be proven, that it is not falsifiable, that it has been falsified, and that it does not make predictions. Using a series of examples, we explain why these criticisms are either false or involve a misunderstanding of the nature of evidential support and scientific knowledge. In the process, we exhibit some of the epistemic principles that are at the heart of scientific inference, and show how they are employed to establish the rational acceptability of evolution.

Keywords

Evolutionary Theory Good Explanation Scientific Theory Perceptual Experience True Belief 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgements 

We would like to thank Matt Frise, Kostas Kampourakis, Lynnette Lounsbury, H. Allen Orr, and Elliott Sober for their helpful comments.

References

  1. Adami, C. 2006. Digital genetics: Unravelling the genetic basis of evolution. Nature Reviews Genetics 7(2): 109–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Alston, W.P. 1993. The reliability of sense perception. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Ayala, F. 1985. The theory of evolution: Recent successes and challenges. In Evolution and creation, ed. Mc.Mullin. Ernan, 59–90. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
  4. Bain, J., and J.D. Norton. 2001. What should philosophers of science learn from the history of the electron? In Histories of the electron: The birth of microphysics, Dibner Institute Studies in the History of Science and Technology, ed. Jed Z. Buchwald and Andrew Warwick, 451–466. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Carroll, S.B. 2006. The making of the fittest: DNA and the ultimate forensic record of evolution. New York: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
  6. Chisholm, R. 1957. Perceiving. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Conee, E., and R. Feldman. 2004. Making sense of skepticism. In Evidentialism, 277–306. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Coyne, J.A. 2009. Why evolution is true. New York: Viking.Google Scholar
  9. Cracraft, J., and M.J. Donoghue (eds.). 2004. Assembling the tree of life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Darwin, C. 1862. On the various contrivances by which British and foreign orchids are fertilised by insects. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
  11. Dawkins, R. 2009. The greatest show on earth: The evidence for evolution. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
  12. Dobzhansky, T. 1973. Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. The American Biology Teacher 35: 125–129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Doolittle, W.F. 2000. Uprooting the tree of life. Scientific American 282(6): 90–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Doolittle, W.F. 2009. The practice of classification and the theory of evolution, and what the demise of Charles Darwin’s tree of life hypothesis means for both of them. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 364(1527): 2221–2228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Duhem, P. 1954/1914. The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Enoch, D., and J. Schechter. 2008. How are basic belief-forming methods justified? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76(3): 547–579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Feldman, R. 2003. Epistemology. Upper Saddle River: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  18. Futuyma, D.J. 2009. Evolution, 2nd ed. Sunderland: Sinauer Associates.Google Scholar
  19. Garland Jr., T., and M.B. Rose. 2009. Experimental evolution: Concepts, methods, and applications of selection experiments. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  20. Gillespie, J.H. 2004. Population genetics: A concise guide, 2nd ed. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Gish, D.T. 1979. Evolution? The fossils say no! San Diego: Creation-Life Publishers.Google Scholar
  22. Glymour, C. 1984. Explanation and realism. In Scientific realism, ed. Jarrett Leplin, 173–192. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  23. Godfrey-Smith, P. 2003. Theory and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of science, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Goldman, A. 1999. Internalism exposed. Journal of Philosophy 96(6): 271–293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Huemer, M. 2001. Skepticism and the veil of perception. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.Google Scholar
  26. Hull, D.L. 1988. Science as a process: An evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Hull, D.L. 1999. The use and abuse of Sir Karl Popper. Biology and Philosophy 14(4): 481–504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Kawecki, T.J., et al. 2012. Experimental evolution. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 27(10): 547–560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Kitcher, P. 1982. Abusing science: The case against creationism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  30. Kritsky, G. 1991. Darwin’s Madagascan Hawk Moth prediction. American Entomologist 37(4): 206–210.Google Scholar
  31. Lakatos, I. 1970. Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In Criticism and the growth of knowledge, proceedings of the international colloquium in the philosophy of science, vol. 4, ed. Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, 91–196. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Lipton, P. 2004. Inference to the best explanation, 2nd ed. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  33. Mayr, E. 1970. Populations, species, and evolution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Mills, S.K., and J.H. Beatty. 1979. The propensity interpretation of fitness. Philosophy of Science 46(2): 263–286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Morris, H.M. 1974. Scientific creationism. San Diego: Creation-Life Publishers.Google Scholar
  36. Norton, J.D. 2000. How we know about electrons. In After Popper, Kuhn and Feyerabend, Recent issues in theories of scientific method, Australasian studies in history and philosophy of science, vol. 15, ed. Robert Nola and Howard Sankey, 67–97. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Orr, H.A. 2009. Fitness and its role in evolutionary genetics. Nature Reviews Genetics 10(8): 531–539.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Patterson, C., D.M. Williams, and C.J. Humphries. 1993. Congruence between molecular and morphological phylogenies. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 24(1): 153–188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Popper, K. 1963. Conjectures and refutations. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  40. Putnam, H. 1974. The ‘corroboration’ of theories. In The philosophy of Karl Popper, Library of living philosophers, vol. 14, ed. Schilpp Paul Arthur, 221–240. La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  41. Scriven, M. 1959. Explanation and prediction in evolutionary theory: Satisfactory explanation of the past is possible even when prediction of the future is impossible. Science 130(3374): 477–482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Sober, E. 2000a. Philosophy of biology, 2nd ed. Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
  43. Sober, E. 2000b. The two faces of fitness. In Thinking about evolution: Historical, philosophical, and political perspectives, ed. Singh Rama Shankar et al., 309–321. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Sober, E. 2008. Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Thagard, P. 1978. The best explanation: Criteria for theory choice. Journal of Philosophy 75(2): 76–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Watson, D.C.C. 1976. The great Brain Robbery. Chicago: Moody Press.Google Scholar
  47. Wilder-Smith, A.E. 1981. The natural sciences know nothing of evolution. San Diego: Creation-Life Publishers.Google Scholar
  48. Woese, C. 1998. The universal ancestor. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 95(12): 6854–6859.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Wysong, R.L. 1976. The creation-evolution controversy. Midland: Inquiry Press.Google Scholar
  50. Zuckerkandl, E., and L. Pauling. 1965. Evolutionary divergence and convergence in proteins. In Evolving genes and proteins, ed. Vernon Bryson and Henry J. Vogel, 97–166. New York: Academic.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of AlabamaBirminghamUSA
  2. 2.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of RochesterRochesterUSA

Personalised recommendations