Social Rules and the Social Background

Chapter
Part of the Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality book series (SIPS, volume 1)

Abstract

How can people function appropriately and respond normatively in social contexts even if they are not aware of rules governing these contexts? John Searle has rightly criticized a popular way out of this problem by simply asserting that they follow them unconsciously. His alternative explanation is based on his notion of a preintentional, nonrepresentational background. In this chapter, I criticize this explanation and the underlying account of the background and suggest an alternative explanation of the normativity of elementary social practices and of the background itself. I propose to think of the background as being intentional, but nonconceptual, and of the basic normativity or proto-normativity as being instituted through common sensory-motor emotional schemata established in the joint interactions of groups. The chapter concludes with some reflections on what role this level of collective intentionality and the notion of the background can play in a layered account of the social mind and the ontology of the social world.

Keywords

Joint Action Intentional State Intentional Content Cooperation Partner Collective Intentionality 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgements 

I acknowledge support for this research by a grant of the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft to the research group “Grenzen der Absichtlichkeit” at the University of Konstanz. I would also like to thank Werner Binder for discussion of an earlier draft and Melynda Moseley for improving my English.

References

  1. Baillargeon, Renee. 2004. Infants’ reasoning about hidden objects: Evidence for event-general and event-specific expectations. Developmental Science 7(4): 391–424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bermúdez, José and Arnon Cahen. 2012. Nonconceptual mental content. In The Stanford ­encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2012 Edition), ed. Edward N. Zalta. Dordrecht: Springer. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2012/entries/content-nonconceptual/
  3. Binder, Werner. 2013. Social ontology, cultural sociology and the war on terror. In The background of social reality: Selected contributions from the inaugural meeting of ENSO, Studies in the philosophy of sociality, vol. 1, eds. Michael Schmitz, Beatrice Kobow, and Hans Bernhard Schmid. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  4. Evans, Gareth. 1982. The varieties of reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Ferraris, Maurizio. 2007. Documentality or why nothing social exists beyond the text. In Cultures. conflict – Analysis – Dialogue, Proceedings of the 29th International Ludwig Wittgenstein-­Symposium in Kirchberg, Austria, ed. Ch. Kanzian and E. Runggaldier, 385–401. Publications of the Austrian Ludwig Wittgenstein Society, New Series, vol. 3.Google Scholar
  6. Gunther, York (ed.). 2003. Essays on nonconceptual content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  7. Langacker, Ronald. 1987/1991. Foundations of cognitive grammar. 2 vols. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Pacherie, Elisabeth. 2011. Nonconceptual representations for action. Social Psychology 42: 67–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Schmid, Hans Bernhard. 2013. Trying to act together – The structure and role of trust in joint action. In The background of social reality: Selected contributions from the inaugural meeting of ENSO, Studies in the philosophy of sociality, vol. 1, eds. Michael Schmitz, Beatrice Kobow, and Hans Bernhard Schmid. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  10. Schmitz, Michael. 2011. Limits of the conscious control of action. Social Psychology 42: 93–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Schmitz, Michael. 2012. The background as intentional, conscious, and nonconceptual. In Knowing without thinking: Mind, action, cognition and the phenomenon of the background, ed. Z. Radman, 57–82. Palgrave: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  12. Searle, John R. 1978. Literal meaning. Erkenntnis 13: 207–224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Searle, John R. 1983. Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Searle, John R. 1990. Consciousness, explanatory inversion, and cognitive science. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13: 585–596.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Searle, John R. 1991. Response. The background of intentionality and action. In John Searle and his critics, ed. E. LePore and R. van Gulick. Cambridge: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  16. Searle, John R. 1992. The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  17. Searle, John R. 1995. The construction of social reality. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
  18. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1984. Philosophische Untersuchungen. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institut für PhilosophieUniversität WienWienAustria

Personalised recommendations