Rerum Concordia Discors: Robustness and Discordant Multimodal Evidence

Chapter
Part of the Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science book series (BSPS, volume 292)

Abstract

Rain today, I reckon, given the grey clouds above, the falling barometer, and after all, it is an autumn day in London. My conjecture is supported with multimodal evidence: the clouds, the barometer, the season. The term “multimodal evidence” will be unfamiliar to most, though it is a common intuition that multimodal evidence is valuable. A “mode” is a way of finding out about the world; a type of evidence; a technique or study design. We usually have evidence for or against a hypothesis which comes from a variety of different modes; I call this multimodal evidence. For example, when devising his laws of motion, Newton had evidence on the orbits of the moons of Jupiter and Saturn, the patterns of spring and neap tides at the solstice and equinox, and terrestrial dynamics. Robustness – the state in which hypotheses are supported with concordant multimodal evidence – is one way in which the value of multimodal evidence has been explicated (Section 9.2). Another way in which multimodal evidence is said to be valuable is based on the notion of security (Section 9.3). An empirical challenge for robustness is that when multimodal evidence is available for a particular hypothesis, it is often discordant (Section 9.4) – discordance is ubiquitous. A conceptual challenge is to know when and how modes are sufficiently independent to count as providing multimodal evidence (Section 9.5). A methodological challenge is that to know the impact multimodal evidence should have on our belief in a hypothesis, the multimodal evidence must be assessed and amalgamated by an amalgamation function (Section 9.6). I argue that an amalgamation function for multimodal evidence should do the following: evidence from multiple modes should be assessed on prior criteria (quality of mode), relative criteria (relevance of mode to a given hypothesis) and posterior criteria (salience of evidence from particular modes and concordance/discordance of evidence between modes); the assessed evidence should be amalgamated; and the output of the function should be a constraint on our justified credence. Without principled methods of amalgamating multimodal evidence, appeals to multimodal evidence are vague and inconclusive. Such amalgamation functions could provide more rigorous guidance for our belief in a hypothesis when presented with multimodal evidence.

Keywords

Multiple Mode Background Assumption Causal History Problematic Assumption Auxiliary Assumption 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Notes

Acknowledgments

I am grateful for detailed feedback from Léna Soler, Emiliano Trizio and members of the UCSD Philosophy of Science Reading Group, especially Nancy Cartwright. I also benefited from discussion with audiences at the 2008 Canadian Society for the History and Philosophy of Science conference, the 2008 Philosophy of Science Association conference, and the 2008 workshop on robustness hosted by the Archives Henri Poincaré, Laboratoire d’Histoire des Sciences et de Philosophie (Nancy-Université).

References

  1. Achinstein, Peter. 2001. The Book of Evidence. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Allamel-Raffin, Catherine. 2005. “De l’intersubjectivité à l’interinstrumentalité: L’exemple de la physique des surfaces.” Philosophia Scientiae 9(1):3–31.Google Scholar
  3. Bechtel, William. 2006. Discovering Cell Mechanisms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Box, George. 1953. “Non-Normality and Tests on Variances.” Biometrika XL:318–35.Google Scholar
  5. Carnap, R. 1950. Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  6. Cartwright, Nancy. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Cartwright, Nancy. 2007. Hunting Causes and Using Them. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chang, Hasok. 2004. Inventing Temperature. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Collins, Harry. 1985. Changing Order: Replication and Induction in Scientific Practice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  10. Culp, Sylvia. 1994. “Defending Robustness: The Bacterial Mesosome as a Test Case.” In Philosophy of Science Association 1994, vol. 1, edited by David Hull, Micky Forbes, and Richard M. Burian, 46–57 Chicago.Google Scholar
  11. Douglas, Heather. 2004. “The Irreducible Complexity of Objectivity.” Synthese 138(3):453–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Fitelson, Branden. 1996. “Wayne, Horwich, and Evidential Diversity.” Philosophy of Science 63:652–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Franklin, Allan. 2002. Selectivity and Discord: Two Problems of Experiment. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
  14. Franklin, Allan, and Colin Howson. 1984. “Why Do Scientists Prefer to Vary Their Experiments?” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 15:51–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Galison, Peter. 1987. How Experiments End. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  16. Hacking, Ian. 1983. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Hempel, Carl. 1966. Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  18. Horwich, Paul. 1982. Probability and Evidence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Howson, Colin, and Peter Urbach. 1989. Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach. La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
  20. Hudson, Robert G. 1999. “Mesosomes: A Study in the Nature of Experimental Reasoning.” Philosophy of Science 66(2):289–309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Jeffrey, Richard. 1965. The Logic of Decision. Chicago: University Of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  22. Keeley, Brian. 2002. “Making Sense of the Senses: Individuating Modalities in Humans and Other Animals.” The Journal of Philosophy 99(1):5–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Kosso, Peter. 2006. “Detecting Extrasolar Planets.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 37:224–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Levins, Richard. 1966. “The Strategy of Model Building in Population Biology.” American Scientist 54:421–31.Google Scholar
  25. Mayo, Deborah. 1996. Error and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  26. Oreskes, Naomi. 1999. The Rejection of Continental Drift. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Rasmussen, Nicolas. 1993. “Facts, Artifacts, and Mesosomes: Practicing Epistemology with the Electron Microscope.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 24(2):221–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Salmon, Wesley. 1984. Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Skyrms, B. 1986. The Dynamics of Rational Deliberation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  30. Staley, Kent. 2004. “Robust Evidence and Secure Evidence Claims.” Philosophy of Science 71:467–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Stegenga, Jacob. 2011. “Is Meta-Analysis the Platinum Standard of Evidence?” Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 42:497–507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Stegenga, Jacob. 2011. “The Chemical Characterization of the Gene: Vicissitudes of Evidential Assessment.” History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 33:103–26.Google Scholar
  33. Trout, J.D. 1993. “Robustness and Integrative Survival in Significance Testing: The World’s Contribution to Rationality.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44:1–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. van Fraassen, Bas. 1989. Laws and Symmetry. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Weber, Marcel. 2005. Philosophy of Experimental Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  36. Westman, Robert. 2011. The Copernican Question: Prognostication, Skepticism, and Celestial Order. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  37. Wimsatt, William. 1981. “Robustness, Reliability, and Overdetermination.” In Scientific Inquiry and the Social Sciences, edited by M. Brewer and B. Collins, 124–63. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of TorontoTorontoCanada

Personalised recommendations