Humean Perspectives on Structural Realism
- 10 Citations
- 874 Downloads
Abstract
Structural Realism (SR) is a moderate variant of scientific realism and can roughly be captured by the idea that we should be committed to the structural rather than object-like content of our best current scientific theories. A quick view on the list of some of the main proponents shows that SR is basically a European philosophy of science movement (and just suits our ESF Programme): John Worrall, Ioannis Votsis, Steven French, Angelo Cei, James Ladyman, Simon Saunders, Michael Esfeld, Vincent Lam, Katherine Brading, Mauro Dorato, Dean Rickles, Fred Muller, and – exceptions prove the rule – Anjan Chakravartty and John Stachel. The list is of course not exhaustive, moreover, the debate has a broad periphery. A notable example of this is Bas van Fraassen’s structural empiricism. The paper is a kind of opinionated review paper. In what follows I will pass through the most prevailing topics in recent debates over SR. My discussion will be organised, perhaps a bit unorthodoxly, in short sections, here and then I will outline my own views.
Keywords
Structural Realism Causal Power Theoretical Term Ontic Structural Realism Humean PerspectivePreview
Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.
References
- Tian Yu Cao (2003). Structural realism and the interpretation of quantum field theory. Synthese 136: 3–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Angelo Cei and Steven French (2006). Looking for structure in all the wrong places: Ramsey sentences, multiple realizability, and structure. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 37: 633–655.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Anjan Chakravartty (2004). Structuralism as a form of scientific realism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 18 (2 & 3): 151-171.Google Scholar
- Anjan Chakravartty (2007). A Metaphysics for Scientific Realism: Knowing the Unobservable. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- William Demopoulos and Michael Friedman (1985). Critical notice: Bertrand Russell’s The Analysis of Matter: Its historical context and contemporary interest. Philosophy of Science 52: 621–639.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Mauro Dorato (2000). Substantivalism, relationism and structural spacetime realism. Foundations of Physics 30(10): 1605-28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Phil Dowe (2000). Physical Causation. New York: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
- Michael Esfeld (2004). Quantum entanglement and a metaphysics of relations. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35(4): 601-617.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Michael Esfeld (in print). The modal nature of structures in ontic structural realism. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
- Michael Esfeld and Vincent Lam (2008). Moderate structural realism about spacetime. Synthese 160: 27-46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bas van Fraassen (2008). Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Steven French (1989). Identity and individuality in classical and quantum physics. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 67: 432–446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Steven French (1998). On the withering away of physical objects. In Elena Castellani (ed.): Interpreting Bodies: Classical and Quantum Objects in Modern Physics, pp. 93–113. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
- Steven French and James Ladyman (2003a). Remodelling structural realism: Quantum physics and the metaphysics of structure. Synthese 136: 31–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Steven French and James Ladyman (2003b). Between platonism and phenomenalism: Reply to Cao. Synthese 136: 73–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Steven French (2006). Structure as a weapon of the realist. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 106: 167–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Richard Healey (2007). Gauging What’s Real: The Conceptual Foundations of Contemporary Gauge Theories. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- James Ladyman and Don Ross (with David Spurrett and John Collier) (2007). Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalised. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Rae Langton (1998). Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- David Lewis (1970). How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy 67: 427–446.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- David Lewis (1986). Philosophical Papers Vol. II. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- David Lewis (2009). Ramseyan Humility. In David Braddon-Mitchell and Robert Nola (eds.): Conceptual Analysis and Philosophical Naturalism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
- Holger Lyre (2004a). Lokale Symmetrien und Wirklichkeit. Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
- Holger Lyre (2004b). Holism and structuralism in U(1) gauge theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 35(4): 643-670.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Holger Lyre (2009). Structural realism and abductive-transcendental arguments. In Michel Bitbol, Pierre Kerszberg and Jean Petitot (eds.): Constituting Objectivity. Transcendental Perspectives on Modern Physics. Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
- Holger Lyre (in print). Is structural underdetermination possible? Synthese.Google Scholar
- Tim Maudlin (2007): The Metaphysics Within Physics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Fred Muller (1998). Structures for Everyone. Amsterdam: Gerits & Son. Fred Muller (in print). Withering away, weakly. Synthese.Google Scholar
- Max Newman (1928). Mr. Russell’s “Causal Theory of Perception”. Mind 37(146): 137-148.Google Scholar
- Willard V. O. Quine (1976). Grades of discriminability. Journal of Philosophy 73(5): 113-116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Michael Redhead (2001). The intelligibility of the universe. In: Anthony O’Hear (ed.): Philosophy at the New Millennium. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Dean Rickles, Steven French and Juha Saatsi (2006). The Structural Foundations of Quantum Gravity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Bertrand Russell (1927). The Analysis of Matter. London: George Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
- Simon Saunders (2003). Structural realism again. Synthese 136: 127–133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Simon Saunders (2006). Are quantum particles objects? Analysis 66: 52–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Jonathan Schaffer (2005). Quiddistic knowledge. Philosophical Studies 123: 1–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Stewart Shapiro (2000). Thinking about Mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Georg Sparber (2009). Unorthodox Humeanism. Frankfurt a.M.: Ontos.Google Scholar
- John Stachel (2002). The relations between things versus the things between relations: The deeper meaning of the hole argument. In: David Malament (ed.): Reading Natural Philosophy: Essays in the History and Philosophy of Science and Mathematics. La Salle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
- Ioannis Votsis (2003). Is structure not enough? Philosophy of Science 70: 879– 890.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- John Worrall (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica 43: 99–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar