The Logic of Campaigning

  • Walter Dean
  • Rohit Parikh
Part of the Lecture Notes in Computer Science book series (LNCS, volume 6521)

Abstract

We consider a political candidate campaigning to be elected. Her chances of being elected will depend on how various groups of voters perceive her, and how they perceive her will depend on what she has said. Different groups of voters may have different preferences and a statement preferred by one group of voters may be disliked by another. Moreover, voters may be optimistic (willing to think the best of the candidate), pessimistic (inclined to expect the worse), or expected value voters, who average over various possibilities which may come about if she is elected. Given these considerations, what should she say? We formalize this problem in propositional logic with certain utility values, and certain intensities of preference for various groups of voters, and show that if the voters are expected value voters, then she is best off being as explicit as possible. Thus a reluctance to be explicit may come about as a result of the presence of optimistic voters.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. AGM.
    Alchourron, C.E., Gardenfors, P., Makinson, D.: On the Logic of Theory Change: Partial Meet Contraction and Revision Functions. The Journal of Symbolic Logic 50(2), 510–530 (1985)MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  2. Arrow.
    Arrow, K.J.: Social Choice and Individual Values. Wiley, New York (1951b); 2nd ed. (1963)MATHGoogle Scholar
  3. Aum.
    Aumann, R.: Agreeing to Disagree. Annals of Statistics 4, 1236–1239 (1976)MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  4. Austin.
    Austin, J.L.: How to Do Things with Words, Oxford (1962)Google Scholar
  5. Bacharach.
    Bacharach, M.: Some Extensions of a Claim of Aumann in an Axiomatic Model of Knowledge. J. Economic Theory 37, 167–190 (1985)MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  6. BF.
    Brams, S., Fishburn, P.: Approval Voting. Springer, Heidelberg (2007); Originally published in 1983 CrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  7. Cave.
    Cave, J.A.K.: Learning to Agree. Economics Letters 12, 147–152 (1983)CrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  8. BJR.
    Benz, A., Jäger, G., Van Rooij, R. (eds.): Game Theory and Pragmatics. Palgrave Studies in Pragmatics, Language and Cognition. Macmillan, Palgrave (2005)Google Scholar
  9. CS.
    Crawford, V.P., Sobel, J.: Strategic information transmission. Econometrica 50(6), 1431–1451 (1982)MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  10. DEL.
    van Ditmarsch, H., van der Hoek, W., Kooi, B.: Dynamic Epistemic Logic. Springer’s Synthese Library Series (2008)Google Scholar
  11. FR.
    Farrell, J., Rabin, M.: Cheap Talk. The Journal of Economic Perspectives 10(3), 103–118 (Summer 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. GP.
    Geanakoplos, J., Polemarchakis, H.: We Can’t Disagree Forever. J. Economic Theory 28, 192–200 (1982)CrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  13. Gibbard.
    Gibbard, A.: Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result. Econometrica 41(4), 587–601 (1973)MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  14. Grice.
    Grice, P.: Studies in the Way of Words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1989)Google Scholar
  15. KM’07.
    Kourousias, G., Makinson, D.: Parallel interpolation, splitting, and relevance in belief change. Journal of Symbolic Logic 72(3), 994–1002 (2007)MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  16. Pa’99.
    Parikh, R.: Belief revision and language splitting. In: Moss, Ginzburg, de Rijke (eds.) Proc. Logic, Language and Computation, CSLI 1999, pp. 266–278 (1999); Earlier version appeared in 1996 in the prliminary proceedingsGoogle Scholar
  17. [Pa’09]
    Parikh, R.: Beth definability, Interpolation and Language Splitting. To appear in the Proceedings of the Beth Symposium, Amsterdam (2009)Google Scholar
  18. PK.
    Parikh, R., Krasucki, P.: Communication, Consensus and Knowledge. Journal of Economic Theory 52, 178–189 (1990)MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  19. PR’03.
    Parikh, R., Ramanujam, R.: A Knowledge based Semantics of Messages. J. Logic, Language and Information 12 (2003)Google Scholar
  20. Pla.
    Plaza, J.A.: Logics of Public Communications, in Knowledge, Rationality & Action, A Special Section of: Synthese. An International Journal for Epistemology, Methodology and Philosophy of Science 158(2), 165–179 (2007)MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  21. Satter.
    Satterthwaite, M.A.: Strategy-proofness and Arrow’s Conditions: Existence and Correspondence Theorems for Voting Procedures and Social Welfare Functions. Journal of Economic Theory 10, 187–217 (1975)MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  22. Sav.
    Savage, L.: The Foundations of Statistics. Dover, New York (1972); Originally published in 1954 by John Wiley and SonsMATHGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  • Walter Dean
    • 1
  • Rohit Parikh
    • 2
    • 3
  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentUniversity of WarwickUK
  2. 2.Brooklyn CollegeUSA
  3. 3.The Graduate Center of CUNYUSA

Personalised recommendations