Advertisement

A Second Naturalization for a Second Nature

  • Ernesto Perini-Santos
Chapter
Part of the Studies in German Idealism book series (SIGI, volume 20)

Abstract

McDowell’s argument to refuse a scientific approach to human rationality is that lawful explanations are unable to account for our rational agency. However, not every scientific explanation is a lawful one. There is another argument to the the same effect: (a) there are distinct inquiries concerning the space of reasons: causal inquiries and constitutive inquiries; (b) they are independent of each other; (c) science addresses only the first sort of questions; (d) therefore, it has no impact on inquiries concerning constitutive features of the space of reasons. I will argue that (b) is false, and therefore (c) is at best unclear. The idea of a second nature suggests more unified view of human knowledge, a sort of Hegelian approach. However, for Hegel, the realm of reason encompasses all of nature, and this is an untenable route towards a full re-enchantment of nature. We should be open to the consequences to our self-understanding of different inquiries of natural sciences about how our second nature emerges and how it unfolds. Once we take account of the different sorts of inquiry in the surroundings of rational agency, we see that we cannot predict in advance how our self-understanding will change as a result of changes in different scientific domains. The concept of second nature gives an appropriate frame to this sort of accommodation.

References

  1. Beran, Michael J., Johannes Brandl, Josef Perner, and Joëlle Proust, eds. 2012. Foundations of Metacognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Bernstein, Jay. 2002. Re-enchanting Nature. In ed. Smith, 217–245.Google Scholar
  3. Bernstein, Richard. 2002. McDowell’s Domesticated Hegelianism. In ed. Smith, 9–24.Google Scholar
  4. Boysen, Sarah T., and Gary G. Berntson. 1995. Responses to Quantity: Perceptual Versus Cognitive Mechanisms in Chimpanzees (Pan Troglodytes). Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes 21 (1): 82–86.Google Scholar
  5. Chemero, Anthony. 2009. Radical Embodied Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  6. Daston, Lorraine. 2014. The Naturalistic Fallacy is Modern. Isis 105 (3): 579–587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Davidson, Donald. 1980. Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  8. Dupré, John. 2012. Processes of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Duque, Félix. 1996. Hegel: de las Complicadas Relaciones entre la Ciencia y las Ciencias. Themata 17: 167–197.Google Scholar
  10. Gomila, Antoni. 2011. The Language of Thought: Still a Game in Town? Teorema 30 (1): 145–155.Google Scholar
  11. Halbig, Christoph. 2008. Varieties of Nature in Hegel and McDowell. In ed. Lindgaard, 72–91.Google Scholar
  12. Hurley, Susan. 2006. Making Sense of Animals. In Rational Animals? ed. S. Hurley and M. Nudds, 139–171. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Illetterati, Luca. 1995. Natura e Ragione. Trento: Verifiche.Google Scholar
  14. Keller, Evelyn F. 2010. The mirage of a space between nature and nurture. Durham/London: Duke University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Macdonald, Graham. 2006. The Two Natures: Another Dogma? In McDowell and his Critics, ed. C. Macdonald and G. Macdonald, 222–235. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Mayr, Ernst. 2004. What Makes Biology Unique. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. McDowell, John. 2011. Perception as a capacity for knowledge. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Morrison, Margaret. 2015. Reconstructing Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Noë, Alva. 2004. Action in Perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  20. Penn, Derek C., Keith J. Holyoak, and Daniel J. Povinelli. 2008. Darwin’s mistake: Explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (2): 109–130.Google Scholar
  21. Pippin, Robert. 2002. Leaving Nature Behind: Or, Two Cheers for Subjectivism. In ed. N. Smith, 58–78.Google Scholar
  22. Proust, Joëlle. 2012. Metacognition and Mindreading: One or Two Functions? In Foundations of Metacognition, ed. M. Beran et al., 234–351. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Proust, Joëlle. 2013. The philosophy of metacognition-mental agency and self-awareness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Sachs, Carl. 2011. The Shape of a Good Question: McDowell, Evolution, and Transcendental Philosophy. Philosophical Forum 42: 61–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Sluga, Hans. 1980. Gottlob Frege. London/New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  26. Sosa, Ernest. 1991. Knowledge in Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. ———. 2007. A Virtue Epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. ———. 2009. Reflective Knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Stone, Alison. 2005. Petrified Intelligence. Albany: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
  30. Tomasello, Michael. 2014. A Natural History of Human Thinking. Cambrdige, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Turri, John. 2013. Bi-Level Virtuous Epistemology. In Virtuous Thoughts: the Philosophy of Ernest Sosa, ed. J. Turri, 147–164. Dordrecth: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Westphal, Kenneth. 2008a. Contemporary Epistemology: Kant, Hegel, McDowell. In ed. Lindgaard, 124–151.Google Scholar
  33. ———. 2008b. Philosophizing about Nature: Hegel’s Philosophical Project. In The Cambridge Companion to Hegel and Nineteenth-Century Philosophy, ed. F. Beiser, 281–310. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  • Ernesto Perini-Santos
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyThe Federal University of Minas Gerais (UFMG)Belo HorizonteBrazil

Personalised recommendations