Skip to main content

When Mechanisms Are Not Enough: The Origin of Eukaryotes and Scientific Explanation

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS,volume 9))

Abstract

The appeal to mechanisms in scientific explanation is commonplace in contemporary philosophy of science. In short, mechanists argue that an explanation of a phenomenon consists of citing the mechanism that brings the phenomenon about. In this paper, we present an argument that challenges the universality of mechanistic explanation: in explanations of the contemporary features of the eukaryotic cell, biologists appeal to its symbiogenetic origin and therefore the notion of symbiogenesis plays the main explanatory role. We defend the notion that symbiogenesis is non-mechanistic in nature and that any attempt to explain some of the contemporary features of the eukaryotic cell mechanistically turns out to be at least insufficient and sometimes fails to address the question that is asked. Finally, we suggest that symbiogenesis is better understood as a pragmatic scientific law and present an alternative non-mechanistic model of scientific explanation. In the model we present, the use of scientific laws is supposed to be a minimal requirement of all scientific explanations, since the purpose of a scientific explanation is to make phenomena expectable. Therefore, this model would help to understand biologists’ appeal to the notion of symbiosis and thus is shown to be better, for the case under examination, than the mechanistic alternative.

This work is fully collaborative; the authors are listed alphabetically.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This point is however controversial, as some people have also defended the idea that other processes such as a phagocytosis might also be considered as the starting point of eukaryocity (e.g. Cavalier-Smith 1989). However, that would not remove the need to explain the origin of mitochondria and chloroplasts in a satisfactory manner, which would lead to the same kind of questions that we mention later. For the purposes of this paper and for simplicity, we will follow Martin’s proposal that equates the origin of eukaryotes with the origin of mitochondria. Thanks to Thomas Bonnin for pointing this out to us.

  2. 2.

    Symbiogenesis is the process of generation of a new biological structure (organ, metabolic pathway, etc.) as a consequence of a long-term symbiotic association. In the case of the eukaryotic cell, symbiogenesis refers to the origin of a complete new biological domain as a consequence of symbiosis. Symbiotic organisms can interact in two different ways: endosymbiotically, if one organism lives within the cell(s) of the other, and ectosymbiotically, when one organism lives on the surface of the cell(s) of the other, but not within them (Archibald 2014). Symbiogenesis is thus a process, whereas endosymbiosis is a state. This distinction has to be kept in mind for the rest of the paper. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging us to clarify this point.

  3. 3.

    Leuridan (2010) argues that for every mechanism we can find an underlying regularity. His conclusion is that the explanatory character of mechanisms lies precisely in these hidden regularities, which actually is conceding too much to the nomological expectability models mechanists were criticizing in the first place.

  4. 4.

    In fact, the notions of entities and activities come from a modification of the previous description of a mechanism in terms of parts and operations/interactions. Bechtel and Glennan still define mechanisms by appealing to the notions of parts and operations/interactions. The motives for their choice can be found in Bechtel and Abrahamsen (2005, fn. 5). Machamer et al. (2000, §3) introduced the new notions of entities and activities, mainly for ontological reasons. We take this not to be a substantive distinction for the purposes of this paper.

  5. 5.

    Earlier in this section we argued, as part of the response to question 1, that it was quite hard to conceive of symbiosis as a factor. We still believe this, for the reasons discussed there, but we are going to assume here that it might serve as one, just for the sake of the argument.

  6. 6.

    In fact it would not even be a mechanism in the sense of “expanded mechanism” as defended by Roe and Baumgaertner (2016), since the problem here is not related to incorporating “pieces” of the environment, as they suggest: the problem is related to the fact that what plays the explanatory role is a regularity.

  7. 7.

    One might still wonder about the exact relationship between mechanisms and regularities in certain explanatory contexts. It is not the aim of this paper to elucidate the nature of that relationship. Nonetheless, some mechanist philosophers have already recognized the use of non-accidental regularities in mechanistic explanations (e.g. Craver and Kaiser 2013; Glennan 1996) and we believe that, in most cases of mechanistic explanation, what does the real explanatory work is the presence of background non-accidental regularities. We plan to develop this line of thought further in a future paper.

  8. 8.

    Of course, the defender of mechanistic explanation might still argue that the appeal to symbiogenesis is not, after all, explanatory. A similar strategy has been pursued by Craver (2008) concerning the explanatory character of the Hodgin-Huxley model of action potential in neurons. However, we believe that pursuing that strategy would violate some basic commitments common to biologists concerning explanation.

  9. 9.

    See also Brandon (1997) for more about biological generalizations having a limited range of nomic necessity and explanatory power.

  10. 10.

    Mitchel also includes other parameters: ontological ones (strength, plus the aforementioned stability) and representational ones (degree of abstraction, simplicity and cognitive manageability), which we take not to be relevant for our purposes in this paper. See Mitchell (2003, chapter 5) for more details.

  11. 11.

    What follows is mainly based on the analysis we already presented in Deulofeu and Suárez (2015).

  12. 12.

    As we said before, the notion of law that we use is Mitchell’s idea of pragmatic law.

  13. 13.

    This reconstruction is merely informal and, due to particular complexities of biological theory, it cannot be made as precise as it could be in the case of classical mechanics. In any case, it has all the elements that are supposed to provide a general idea concerning embedding.

References

  • Alleva, K., J. Díez, and L. Federico. 2017. Models, theory structure and mechanisms in biochemistry: The case of allosterism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 63: 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Archibald, J. 2014. One plus one equals one: Symbiosis and the evolution of complex life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Endosymbiosis and eukaryotic cell evolution. Current Biology 25: R911–R921.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audesirk, T., G. Audesirk, and B.E. Byers. 2008. Biology: Life on earth. Hoboken: Pearson Education.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balzer, W., C.U. Moulines, and J.D. Sneed. 2012. An architectonic for science: The structuralist program. Vol. 186. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. 2006. Discovering cell mechanisms: The creation of modern cell biology. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. 2011. Mechanism and biological explanation. Philosophy of Science 78 (4): 533–557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., and A. Abrahamsen. 2005. Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 36 (2): 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., and R.C. Richardson. 1993. Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as scientific research strategies. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R.N. 1997. Does biology have laws? The experimental evidence. Philosophy of Science 64: S444–S457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cavalier-Smith, T. 1989. Archaebacteria and Archezoa. Nature 339: 100–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Symbiogenesis: Mechanisms, evolutionary consequences, and systematic implications. Annual Review of Ecology, Evolution, and Systematics 44: 145–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C.F. 2006. When mechanistic models explain. Synthese 153 (3): 355–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Explaining the brain. New York: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Physical law and mechanistic explanation in the Hodgkin and Huxley model of the action potential. Philosophy of Science 75: 1022–1033.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C.F., and M.I. Kaiser. 2013. Mechanisms and laws: Clarifying the debate. In Mechanism and causality in biology and economics, ed. H.K. Chao, S.T. Chen, and R.L. Millstein, vol. 3, 125–145. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., and C.F. Craver. 2002. Strategies in the interfield discovery of the mechanism of protein synthesis. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33 (1): 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deulofeu, R., and J. Suárez. 2015. On the explanatory character of Margulis’ theory of the origin of the eukaryotic cell. In Proceedings of the VIII Meeting of the Spanish society for logic, methodology and philosophy of science, ed. J.A. Díez, M. García-Carpintero, J. Martínez, and S. Oms, 276–280. Barcelona: Universitat de Barcelona.

    Google Scholar 

  • Díez, J.A. 2002. Explicación, unificación y subsunción. In Diversidad de la explicación científica, ed. W.J. González, 73–96. Barcelona: Ariel.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Scientific w-explanation as ampliative, specialised embedding: a neo-hempelian account. Erkenntnis 79: 1413–1443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dolan, M.F. 2013. Endosymbiosis and the origin of eukaryotes. In Evolution from the Galapagos: Two centuries after Darwin, ed. G. Trueba and C. Montúfar, 125–128. New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, A.E. 2010. The symbiotic habit. Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. 1996. Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis 44 (1): 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science 69 (S3): S342–S353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gruber-Vodicka, H.R., U. Dirks, N. Leisch, C. Baranyi, K. Stoecker, S. Bulgheresi, N.R. Heindl, M. Horn, C. Lott, A. Loy, M. Wagner, and J. Ott. 2011. Paracatenula, an ancient symbiosis between thiotrophic Alphaproteobacteria and catenulid flatworms. PNAS of the United States of America 108 (29): 12078–12083.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. 1965. Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C., and P. Oppenheim. 1948. Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science 15 (2): 135–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1970. Second thoughts on paradigms. In The structure of scientific theories, ed. F. Suppe, 459–482. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leuridan, B. 2010. Can mechanisms really replace laws of nature? Philosophy of Science 77 (3): 317–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., L. Darden, and C.F. Craver. 2000. Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67 (1): 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margulis, L. 1970. Origin of eukaryotic cells: Evidence and research implications. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, W.F., M. Roettger, T. Kloesges, T. Thiergart, C. Woehle, S. Gould, and T. Dagan. 2012. Modern endosymbiotic theory: Getting lateral gene transfer into the equation. Journal of Ensocytobiosis and Cell Research 23: 1–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, W.F., S. Garg, and V. Zimorski. 2015. Endosymbiotic theories for eukaryote origin. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 370: 20140330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S.D. 1997. Pragmatic laws. Philosophy of Science 64: S468–S479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Dimensions of scientific law. Philosophy of Science 67 (2): 242–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Biological complexity and integrative pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, N., and D.B. Sloan. 2015. The hologenome concept: Helpful or hollow? PLoS Biology 13 (12): e1002311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nicholson, D.J. 2012. The concept of mechanism in biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 43 (1): 152–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley, M. 2010. The first eukaryote cell: An unfinished history of contestation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 41 (3): 212–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raff, R.A., and H.R. Mahler. 1972. The non symbiotic origin of mitochondria. Science 177: 575–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roe, S.M., and B. Baumgaertner 2016. Extended mechanistic explanations: Expanding the current mechanistic conception to include more complex biological systems. Journal for General Philosophy of Science 48: 517–534

    Google Scholar 

  • Sagan, L. 1967. On the origin of mitosing cells. Journal of Theoretical Biology 14: 225–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sapp, J. 2010. Saltational symbiosis. Theory Biosciences 129: 125–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spang, A., J.H. Saw, S.L. Jørgensen, K. Zaremba-Niedzwiedzka, J. Martijn, A.E. Lind, R. van Eijk, C. Schleper, L. Guy, and T.J.G. Ettema. 2015. Complex Archaea that bridge the gap between prokaryotes and eukaryotes. Nature 521: 173–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stearns, S.C., and R.F. Hoekstra. 2000. Evolution. An introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uzzel, T., and C. Spolsky. 1974. Mitochondria and plastids as endosymbionts: A revival of special creation? American Scientist 62: 334–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, T.A., and T.M. Embley. 2015. Changing ideas about eukaryotic origins. Philosophical transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B 370: 20140318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. 1997. Explanation, invariance, and intervention. Philosophy of Science 64: S26–S41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Explanation and invariance in the special sciences. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (2): 197–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Making things happen. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Scientific explanation. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/scientific-explanation/

Download references

Acknowledgments

Different versions of this paper were presented at the VIII Meeting of the Spanish Society for Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science (University of Barcelona, 2015) and the III Conference of the German Society for the Philosophy of Science (University of Düsseldorf, 2016). We would like to thank all the participants for their helpful comments and suggestions. We would also like to thank Thomas Bonnin, Mark Canciani, José Díez, John Dupré, Çağlar Karaca, Adrian Stencel and an anonymous referee, who read previous versions of this paper and made helpful comments and suggestions. Finally, the Spanish Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness (FFI2016-767999-P) and the Fundación Bancaria la Caixa are formally acknowledged for their economic support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roger Deulofeu .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Deulofeu, R., Suárez, J. (2018). When Mechanisms Are Not Enough: The Origin of Eukaryotes and Scientific Explanation. In: Christian, A., Hommen, D., Retzlaff, N., Schurz, G. (eds) Philosophy of Science. European Studies in Philosophy of Science, vol 9. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-72577-2_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics