Skip to main content

Agrammaticality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
New Essays on Frege

Part of the book series: Nordic Wittgenstein Studies ((NRWS,volume 3))

  • 309 Accesses

Abstract

In this paper I begin by scrutinizing classic approaches to the question of agrammaticality, with a particular focus on Frege and the early Wittgenstein, and try to show that a further step is needed in order to adequately address this topic. I then focus on the later Wittgenstein’s treatment of nonsense-poems and claim that the failure of the Philosophical Investigations as a book is actually connected with Wittgenstein’s recognition that philosophy should be written under the form of poetry. The therapeutic consequences of this view are discussed in connection with Deleuze’s comments on Melville and with Read’s comments on Sass, which offer very different views of agrammaticality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cf. Wittgenstein (1922, 5.473 and 5.4733). See also 3.325, where Wittgenstein speaks of “rules of logical grammar —of logical syntax ”, and 3.344, where he simply refers to “rules of logical syntax ”. The notion of “logical syntax ” also appears in 3.33 and 6.124.

  2. 2.

    Cf. Heidegger (1998, 84ff) .

  3. 3.

    Cf. Carnap (1959, 69–73) .

  4. 4.

    For a discussion of the two traditional readings of the Tractatus, the positivist and the metaphysical, in contrast with the resolute reading of the book, see, for example , Conant (2002) . In this paper, Conant , after Diamond (1991) , discusses at length some of the passages I have alluded to.

  5. 5.

    See in addition Wittgenstein (2009, §261), where he also refers to the idea of “inarticulate sound ”.

  6. 6.

    See in addition Wittgenstein (2009, §134), where it is said apropos of the sentence “This is how things are” that “one feature of our concept of a proposition is sounding like one” (translation slightly modified).

  7. 7.

    References follow G. H. von Wright’s catalogue of the Wittgenstein papers and are by MS or TS number .

  8. 8.

    This is actually reminiscent of what Frege says in §31 of the Basic Laws of Arithmetic , namely: “Our simple names denote [bedeuten] something” or “always have a denotation [Bedeutung ]” (1893/1964, 47/87). See in this regard Weiner (2002).

  9. 9.

    This typescript consists of a partial translation of the first half of the “early” or “pre-war” version of the Investigations, thoroughly revised by Wittgenstein . The German text is to be found in TS 220, 8, deriving from MS 142, 10.

  10. 10.

    See Wittgenstein (2009, §§19–20) .

  11. 11.

    In an early version of this remark, there is a variant for the beginning of the second paragraph, which reads: “But the fairy tale only speaks falsehood; not nonsense !” (2000, MS 124, 239, my translation)

  12. 12.

    Luckhardt and Aue render “Dichtungen” by “works of literature ”, but “poems” seems to capture more adequately what Wittgenstein has in mind here.

  13. 13.

    This remark occurs in the context of a critical discussion of “calculation as experiment” and within quotation marks, suggesting that Wittgenstein would separate poetry from experiment. Smyth (1997, 228) alludes exactly to “Wittgenstein’s distinction between poetry and ‘psychological experiment’”, but he also writes that “Wittgenstein’s analogous distinction between prediction and proof, experiment and calculation, did not prevent him from considering proofs predictions or metapredictions about future events”. Indeed, Wittgenstein seems to accept that the poet makes a kind of psychological experiment when he writes a poem.

  14. 14.

    In a manuscript version of this remark, Wittgenstein wrote “Do we finally understand [. . .]” (2000, MS 140, 6, my translation).

  15. 15.

    See Schalkwyk (2004, 72–73), Schroeder (2006, 125–126), Brusotti (2009, 346) and Schulte (2013, 349–352) .

  16. 16.

    Wittgenstein’s words remind us of those of Frege in his Foundations of Arithmetic when it is said that “only if every gap [Lücke] in the chain of deductions is eliminated with the greatest care can we say with certainty upon what primitive truths the proof depends” (1884/1980, §4).

  17. 17.

    Talking about dreaming , Wittgenstein ascribes the idea of a “dynamical theory ” to Freud in MS 157a, 56v, in a note from the beginning of 1937, and explicitly mentions Freud’s “‘dynamic’ theory of dreams ” in TS 239, 74. This remark in the so-called “revised early version” of the Investigations would make its way into the collection of cuttings published as Zettel (§444). Compare this with the aforementioned passage from Wittgenstein’s “Dictation for Schlick ”, in which he says that “[o]ur method resembles psychoanalysis ”.

  18. 18.

    See, for example , Stern (1995, 39–40).

  19. 19.

    Cf. Melville (1996, 32ff) .

  20. 20.

    Compare the notion of “inarticulate block” with Wittgenstein’s notion of “inarticulate sound ” alluded to above.

  21. 21.

    Compare Wittgenstein’s similar procedure in the above-quoted remark about “perfection” (1998, 67).

  22. 22.

    It is noteworthy that Artaud is the author of “An Antigrammatical Effort Against Lewis Carroll ”, which consists of a peculiar translation of “Jabberwocky” into French.

  23. 23.

    See Wittgenstein (1979b, 92), as well as Wittgenstein (1922, 5.641).

  24. 24.

    A study of this kind can be found in Venturinha (2011).

  25. 25.

    I find Read’s affirmation that “Winch looks at what the Azande are doing with and alongside their words [. . .]” (2001, 458) incomprehensible.

  26. 26.

    For Read (2001, 472, n. 37), they do not constitute an alternative “way of being-in-the-world”; they form “various ways of … not being-in-the-world at all”. But his ellipsis shows the opposite.

  27. 27.

    Material included in this paper was presented in events in Innsbruck and Lisbon in 2011, Strasbourg in 2012, Athens in 2013 as well as in Lisbon again in 2015. I would like to thank the participants in these meetings for stimulating discussions. I would also like to thank Andrew Lugg , Gisela Bengtsson, Simo Säätelä and Rob Vinten for helpful comments. This paper was written as a contribution to the research project “Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: Re-Evaluating a Project” (2010–2013) funded by the Portuguese Foundation for Science and Technology.

References

  • Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2005). Wittgenstein: Understanding and meaning: Volume 1 of an analytical commentary on the Philosophical Investigations, exegesis §§1–184. P. M. S. Hacker(Ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brusotti, M. (2009). Wittgensteins Nietzsche: Mit vergleichenden Betrachtungen zur Nietzsche-Rezeption im Wiener Kreis. Nietzsche-Studien, 38, 335–362.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1959). The elimination of metaphysics through logical analysis of language. A. Pap, (Trans.). In A. J. Ayer (Ed.), Logical positivism (pp. 60–81). New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, L. (1994). Through the looking-glass. London: Puffin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conant, J. (2002). The method of the Tractatus. In E. H. Reck (Ed.), From Frege to Wittgenstein: Perspectives on early analytic philosophy (pp. 374–462). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984). What metaphors mean. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Inquiries into truth and interpretation (pp. 245–264). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (1998). Essays critical and clinical. D. W. Smith & M. A. Greco (Trans.). London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, C. (1991). Frege and nonsense. In C. Diamond (Ed.), The realistic spirit: Wittgenstein, philosophy, and the mind (pp. 73–79). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1981). Frege: Philosophy of language. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1884/1980). Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik: Eine logisch mathematische Untersuchung über den Begriff der Zahl. Breslau: W. Koebner. English edition: Frege, G. (1980). The foundations of arithmetic: A logico-mathematical enquiry into the concept of number (2nd rev. ed., 5th impr. with corr.). J. L. Austin (Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892/1980). Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 100, 25–50. English edition: Frege, G. (1980). On sense and meaning. M. Black, (Trans.). In P. Geach & M. Black (Eds.), Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (pp. 56–78). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1893/1964). Grundgesetze der Arithmetik: Begriffsschriftlich abgeleitet (Vol. I). Jena: Hermann Pohle. English edition: Frege, G. (1964). The basic laws of arithmetic: Exposition of the system. M. Furth (Ed. & Trans.). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1998). What is metaphysics? D. F. Krell, (Trans.). In M. Heidegger, Pathmarks (pp. 82–96). W. McNeill (Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1998). Critique of pure reason. P. Guyer & A. W. Wood (Ed. & Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klement, K. C. (2002). Frege and the logic of sense and reference. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lugg, A. (2004). Wittgenstein’s Investigations 1–133: A guide and interpretation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melville, H. (1996). Bartleby, the scrivener: A story of Wall-Street. In H. Melville (Ed.), The Piazza tales (pp. 15–52). New York: The Modern Library.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitcher, G. (1986). Wittgenstein, nonsense, and Lewis Carroll. In S. Shanker (Ed.), Ludwig Wittgenstein: Critical assessments (Vol. 4, pp. 398–415). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Read, R. (2001). On approaching schizophrenia through Wittgenstein. Philosophical Psychology, 14, 449–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, L. (1994). The paradoxes of delusion: Wittgenstein, Schreber, and the schizophrenic mind. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schalkwyk, D. (2004). Wittgenstein’s “imperfect garden”: The ladders and labyrinths of philosophy as Dichtung. In J. Gibson & W. Huemer (Eds.), The literary Wittgenstein (pp. 55–74). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, S. (2006). Wittgenstein: The way out of the fly-bottle. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schulte, J. (2013). Wittgenstein on philosophy and poetry. In M. F. Molder, D. Soeiro, & N. Fonseca (Eds.), Morphology: Questions on method and language (pp. 347–360). Bern: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smyth, J. V. (1997). A glance at SunSet: Numerical fundaments in Frege, Wittgenstein, Shakespeare, Beckett. In B. H. Smith & A. Plotnitsky (Eds.), Mathematics, science, and postclassical theory (pp. 212–242). Durham: Duke University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, D. (1995). Wittgenstein on mind and language. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Venturinha, N. (2011). Wittgenstein reads Nietzsche: The roots of Tractarian solipsism. In E. Ramharter (Ed.), Unsocial sociabilities: Wittgenstein’s sources (pp. 59–74). Berlin: Parerga.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiner, J. (2002). Section 31 revisited: Frege’s elucidations. In E. H. Reck (Ed.), From Frege to Wittgenstein: Perspectives on early analytic philosophy (pp. 149–182). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. C. K. Ogden (Trans.). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Philosophical grammar. R. Rhees. (Ed.), A. Kenny (Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1979a). Wittgenstein and the Vienna Circle: Conversations recorded by Friedrich Waismann. B. McGuinness (Ed.), J. Schulte & B. McGuinness (Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1979b). Notebooks 1914–1916. G. H. von Wright & G. E. M Anscombe (Eds.), G. E. M. Anscombe (Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1980). Wittgenstein’s lectures: Cambridge, 1930–1932. D. Lee (Ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1981b). Zettel. G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. von Wright (Eds.), G. E. M. Anscombe (Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1998). Culture and value: A selection from the posthumous remains (2nd ed.). G. H. von Wright with H. Nyman (Ed.), A. Pichler (Rev. Ed.), P. Winch (Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2000). Wittgenstein’s Nachlass: The Bergen electronic edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2005). The Big Typescript: TS 213. C. G. Luckhardt & M. A. E. Aue (Eds. & Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2009). Philosophical investigations. P. M. S. Hacker & J. Schulte (Eds.), G. E. M Anscombe, P. M. S. Hacker, & J. Schulte (Trans.). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L., & Waismann, F. (2003). The voices of Wittgenstein: The Vienna Circle. G. Baker (Ed.), G. Baker, M. Mackert, J. Connolly, & V. Politis (Trans.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nuno Venturinha .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Venturinha, N. (2018). Agrammaticality. In: Bengtsson, G., Säätelä, S., Pichler, A. (eds) New Essays on Frege. Nordic Wittgenstein Studies, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-71186-7_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics