Advertisement

What is a Computer Simulation and What does this Mean for Simulation Validation?

  • Claus BeisbartEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Simulation Foundations, Methods and Applications book series (SFMA)

Abstract

Many questions about the fundamentals of some area take the form “What is …?” It does not come as a surprise then that, at the dawn of Western philosophy, Socrates asked the questions of what piety, courage, and justice are. Nor is it a wonder that the philosophical preoccupation with computer simulations centered, among other things, about the question of what computer simulations are. Very often, this question has been answered by stating that computer simulation is a species of a well-known method, e.g., experimentation. Other answers claim at least a close relationship between computer simulation and another method. In any case, correct answers to the question of what a computer simulation is should help us to better understand what validation of simulations is. The aim of this chapter is to discuss the most important proposals to understand computer simulation in terms of another method and to trace consequences for validation. Although it has sometimes been claimed that computer simulations are experiments, there are strong reasons to reject this view. A more appropriate proposal is to say that computer simulations often model experiments. This implies that the simulation scientists should to some extent imitate the validation of an experiment. But the validation of computer simulations turns out to be more comprehensive. Computer simulations have also been conceptualized as thought experiments or close cousins of the latter. This seems true, but not very telling since thought experiments are not a standard method and since it is controversial how they contribute to our acquisition of knowledge. I thus consider a specific view on thought experiments to make some progress on understanding simulations and their validation. There is finally a close connection between computer simulation and modeling, and it can be shown that the validation of a computer simulation is the validation of a specific model, which may either be thought to be mathematical or fictional.

Keywords

Definition Experiments Thought experiments Argumentation Models Internal vs. external validity 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I’m grateful to Julie Jebeile and Nicole J. Saam for useful comments and criticism.

References

  1. Baumberger, C., Knutti, R., & Hirsch Hadorn, G. (2017). Building confidence in climate model projections: An analysis of inferences from fit. WIREs Climate Change, 8(3), e454.Google Scholar
  2. Beisbart, C. (2012). How can computer simulations produce new knowledge? European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2(3), 395–434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Beisbart, C. (2014). Are we sims? How computer simulations represent and what this means for the simulation argument. The Monist, 97(3), 399–417, (special issue edited by P. Humphreys).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Beisbart, C. (2018). Are computer simulations experiments? And if not, how are they related to each other? European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 8(2), 171–204.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-017-0181-5.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Beeler, J. R. (1983). Radiation effects computer experiments. Amsterdam etc: North-Holland.Google Scholar
  6. Brown, J. R. (1991). The laboratory of the mind: Thought experiments in the natural sciences. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  7. Brown, J. R. (2004). Peeking into Plato’s haeven. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1126 –1138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Brown, J. R., & Fehige, Y. (2017). Thought experiments. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/thought-experiment/.
  9. Campbell, D. T. (1957). Factors relevant to the validity of experiments in social settings. Psychological Bulletin, 54(4), 297–312.  https://doi.org/10.1037/h0040950.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Campbell, D. T., & Stanley, J. C. (1963). Experimental and quasi-experimental designs for research. In N. L. Gale (Ed.), Handbook of research on teaching (pp. 88ff). Chicago, IL: Rand McNally.Google Scholar
  11. Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Cook, T. D., & Campbell, D. T. (1979). Quasi-experimentation: Design & analysis issues for field settings. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company.Google Scholar
  13. Einstein, A. (1961). Relativity, the special and the general theory. A Popular Exposition. London: Methuen (1920, here quoted after edition published by Crown, New York).Google Scholar
  14. El Skaf, R., & Imbert, C. (2013). Unfolding in the empirical sciences: experiments, thought experiments and computer simulations. Synthese, 190(16), 3451–3474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Franklin, A., & Perovic, S. (2016). Experiment in physics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/physics-experiment/.
  16. Frigg, R., & Hartmann, S. (2017). Models in science. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/models-science/.
  17. Frigg, R. P., & Reiss, J. (2009). The philosophy of simulation: Hot new issues or same old stew? Synthese, 169, 593–613.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Gendler, T. S. (2004). Thought experiments rethought and reperceived. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1152–1163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Gupta, A. (2015). Definitions. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/definitions/.
  20. Hartmann, S. (1996). The World as a process: Simulations in the natural and social sciences. In R. Hegselmann et al. (Eds.), Modelling and simulation in the social sciences from the philosophy of science point of view, Theory and decision library (pp. 77-100). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  21. Heidelberger, M. (2005). Experimentation and instrumentation. In D. Borchert (Ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy. Appendix (pp. 12–20). New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  22. Hughes, R. I. G. (1997). Models and representation. Philosophy of Science (Proceedings), 64, S325–S336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Humphreys, P. (2004). Extending ourselves: Computational science, empiricism, and scientific method. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Humphreys, P. (2009). The philosophical novelty of computer simulation methods. Synthese, 169, 615–626.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Imbert, C. (2017). Computer simulations and computational models in science. In L. Magnani & T. Bertolotti (Eds.), Springer handbook of model-based science (Vol. 34, pp. 733–779). Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
  26. Koblick, D. C. (1959). An enzymatic ion exchange model for active sodium transport. The Journal of General Physiology, 42(3), 635–645.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Lenhard, J. (2011). Epistemologie der Iteration. Gedankenexperimente und Simulationsexperimente. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 59(1), 131–145.Google Scholar
  28. Liu, J., Wang, M., Chen, S., & Robbins, M. O. (2010). Molecular simulations of electroosmotic flows in rough nanochannels. Journal of Computational Physics, 229(20), 7834–7847.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Massimi, M., & Bhimji, W. (2015). Computer simulations and experiments: The case of the Higgs boson. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 512, 71–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Morrison, M. (2009). Models, measurement and computer simulation: The changing face of experimentation. Philosophical Studies, 143, 33–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Morrison, M. (2015). Reconstructing reality: Models, mathematics, and simulations. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Naumova, E. N., Gorski, J., & Naumov, Y. N. (2008). Simulation studies for a multistage dynamic process of immune memory response to influenza: Experiment in silico. Annales Zoologici Fennici, 45, 369–384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Nersessian, N. J. (1992). In the Theoretician’s laboratory: Thought experimenting as mental modeling. In PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association (Vol. 1992, pp. 291–301).Google Scholar
  34. Nersessian, Nancy J. (2007). Thought experimenting as mental modeling. Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 7(2), 125–161.Google Scholar
  35. Newton, P., & Shaw, S. (2014). Validity in educational and psychological assessment. London: SAGE Publications.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Norton, J. D. (1996). Are thought experiments just what you thought? Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26, 333–366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Norton, J. D. (2004a). On Thought experiments: Is there more to the argument?. In Proceedings of the 2002 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. Philosophy of Science (Vol. 71, pp. 1139–1151).MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Norton, J. D. (2004b). Why thought experiments do not transcend empiricism. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in the philosophy of science. Blackwell: Oxford, pp. 44–66.Google Scholar
  39. Parker, W. S. (2008). Franklin, Holmes, and the epistemology of computer simulation. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 22(2), 165–183.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Parker, W. (2009). Does matter really matter? Computer Simulations, Experiments, and Materiality, Synthese, 169, 483–496.Google Scholar
  41. Radder, H. (2009). The philosophy of scientific experimentation: A review. Automatic Experimentation 1. Open access. http://www.aejournal.net/content/1/1/2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Saam, N. J. S. (2017). What is a computer simulation? A Review of a Passionate Debate, Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 48(2), 293–309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Schlesinger, S. et al. (1979). Terminology for Model Credibility, Simulation, 32, 103–104.Google Scholar
  44. Suárez, M. (2004). An inferential conception of scientific representation. Philosophy of Science, 71, 767–779.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Verlet, L. (1967). Computer “experiments” on classical fluids. I. Thermodynamical properties of Lennard-Jones molecules. Physical Review, 159(1), 98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Weisberg, M. (2007). Who is a modeler? British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 58, 207–233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Winsberg, E. (2001). Simulations, models, and theories: Complex physical systems and their representations. In Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science (Vol. 68, pp. 442–454).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Winsberg, E. (2003). Simulated experiments: Methodology for a virtual world. Philosophy of Science, 70, 105–125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Winsberg, E. (2009). A tale of two methods. Synthese, 169, 483–496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute of PhilosophyUniversity of BernBernSwitzerland

Personalised recommendations