Advertisement

The Enlightenment: Truths Behind a Misleading Abstraction

  • Robert NolaEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Science: Philosophy, History and Education book series (SPHE)

Abstract

What does the nominalization ‘The Enlightenment’ refer to? Sometimes it is used merely to name a period of time in European history. Sometimes it is use to refer to a movement or a process (social or intellectual). Again, it is used to refer to some body of doctrine (though often what doctrine is unclear). On other occasions, it is used to refer to people who advanced such bodies of doctrine. Contexts of use may not be sufficient to determine the referent of ‘The Enlightenment’. Such a nominalization is to be contrasted with the use of the adjective ‘enlightened’ to name some property of a person. This paper attempts to say what this property is and show how it underpins an epidemiology of being enlightened , that is, an account of the distribution of enlightened as opposed to unenlightened people in a given society at a given time. This gives the kernel of truth that the nominalization ‘The Enlightenment’ obscures. It also helps show that some recent criticisms of “The Enlightenment” fall quite short of their mark.

References

  1. Bittner, R. (1996). What is enlightenment? In Schmidt (Ed.) (1996) pp. 345–358.Google Scholar
  2. Brickhouse, N. W. (2001). Embodying science: A feminist perspective on learning. Journal of Research in Science Teaching, 38(3), 282–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bristow, W. (2010). Enlightenment. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. URL = http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/enlightenment/. Accessed 26 Apr 2016.
  4. Cassirer, E. (1951/1932). The philosophy of the enlightenment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Coyne, J. A. (2015). Faith vs. fact: Why science and religion are incompatible. New York: Viking.Google Scholar
  6. Ferrone, V. (2015). The enlightenment: History of an idea. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Gay, P. (1967). The enlightenment: An interpretation: Volume 1, the rise of modern paganism. London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson.Google Scholar
  8. Gay, P. (1970). The enlightenment: An interpretation: Volume 2, the science of freedom. London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson.Google Scholar
  9. Gelfert, A. (2014). A critical introduction to testimony. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
  10. Goldstein, R. (2015,May). Don’t overthink it. Review of Matthew B. Crawford, The world beyond your head: On becoming an individual in an age of distraction. In The Atlantic monthly (pp. 50–52). Boston: The Atlantic Co.Google Scholar
  11. Gould, S. J. (1999). Rocks of ages: Science and religion and the fullness of life. New York: Ballantine.Google Scholar
  12. Gray, J. (2002). False dawn: The delusions of global capitalism. London: Granta Books.Google Scholar
  13. Gray, J. (2008). Black mass: Apocalyptic religion and the death of utopia. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  14. Habermas, J. (1990). The philosophical discourse of modernity: Twelve lectures. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  15. Honneth, A., McCarthy, T., Offe, C., & Wellmer, A. (Eds.). (1992). Philosophical interventions in the unfinished project of enlightenment. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  16. Horkheimer, M., & Adorno, T. (1994/1944/1947). The dialectics of enlightenment (Cumming J., Trans). New York: Continuum.Google Scholar
  17. Hume, D. (1985). Of national characters. In E. F. Miller (Ed.), David Hume: Essays moral, political and literary (pp. 197–215). Indianapolis: Liberty Classics.Google Scholar
  18. Israel, J. I. (2006). Enlightenment contested. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Israel, J. I. (2011). Democratic enlightenment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Kant, I. (1996/1784). An answer to the question: What is enlightenment? In J. Schmidt (Ed.) (1996) pp. 58–64.Google Scholar
  21. Locke, J. (1689/2010–15). ‘Toleration’ (or ‘First letter on toleration’) translated by Jonathan Bennett. http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/assets/pdfs/locke1689b.pdf. Accessed 20 Apr 2016.
  22. Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1983). Letter of Marx to Engels, 15 August 1857. Collected works volume 40. Marx and Engels 1856–1859. London: Lawrence and Wishart.Google Scholar
  23. Matthews, M. R. (2015). Science teaching: The contribution of history and philosophy of science. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  24. Mendelssohn, M. (1784/1996). On the question: What is Enlightenment? In Schmidt (Ed.) (1996): pp. 53–57.Google Scholar
  25. Pocock, J. G. A. (1999). Barbarism and religion: Volume 1, the enlightenments of Edward Gibbon, 1737–1764. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Schmidt, J. (Ed.). (1996). What is enlightenment? Eighteenth-century answers and twentieth- century questions. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  27. Schmidt, J. (2000). Genocide and the limits of enlightenment: Horkheimer and adorno revisited. In Stråth and Kaye (Eds.) (2000), pp. 81–102.Google Scholar
  28. Shimony, A. (1997). Some historical and philosophical reflections on science and enlightenment. In L. Darden (Ed.), Proceedings of the 1996 PSA meeting (pp. S1–S14). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
  29. Sperber, D. (1996). Explaining culture: A naturalistic approach. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  30. Stråth, B., & Kaye, J. (Eds.). (2000). Enlightenment and genocide, contradictions of modernity (philosophy and politics, volume 5). Brussels: Peter Lang International Academic Publishers.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing AG 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.School of HumanitiesThe University of AucklandAucklandNew Zealand

Personalised recommendations