Advertisement

Evaluating Relevance and Commitments in Rhetorical Straw Man

  • Fabrizio Macagno
  • Douglas Walton
Chapter
Part of the Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology book series (PEPRPHPS, volume 14)

Abstract

This chapter is focused on rhetorical strategies based on indirect reporting and distortion of a party’s viewpoint. We begin by clarifying the role of the notion of argumentative relevance for assessing when a viewpoint is correctly reported or manipulated. We will describe relevance as a sequential concept referring to the number of premises and intermediate arguments to connect a move (the interpretation of a move in this case) to the issue or claim discussed or to be proved (the original move in this case). A formal model of dialogue for evaluating misreports and the corresponding strategies (straw man fallacy) is constructed, providing a normative dialectical framework that can guide an analyst in the tasks of detecting, representing, criticizing and justifying a distortion of a viewpoint. We will outline five straw man rhetorical techniques that can be used both for helping us identify and understand the straw man as a fallacy and for illustrating how fallacious arguments of this type can be used to cleverly persuade a target audience.

Keywords

Relevance Formal model of Dialogue Straw man Argumentation Interpretation Pragmatics Implicatures Fallacies 

References

  1. Aikin, S. F., & Casey, J. (2011). Straw men, weak men, and hollow men. Argumentation, 25(1), 87–105. http://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-010-9199-y CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Allen, J. (2007). Rhetoric and logic. In I. Worthington (Ed.), A companion to Greek rhetoric (pp. 350–364). Malden: Blackwell Publishing. http://doi.org/10.1111/b.9781405125512.2007.00027.x CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Aristotle. (1991). Topics. In J. Barnes (Ed.), The complete works of Aristotle (Vol. I). Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Bizer, G. Y., Kozak, S. M., & Holterman, L. A. (2009). The persuasiveness of the straw man rhetorical technique. Social Influence, 4(3), 216–230. http://doi.org/10.1080/15534510802598152 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bosanac, P. (2009). Litigation logic: A practical guide to effective argument. Chicago: American Bar Association.Google Scholar
  6. Braet. (1999). Aristotle’s almost unnoticed contribution to the doctrine of stasis. Mnemosyne, 52(4), 408–433. http://doi.org/10.1163/156852599323283559 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Capone, A. (2016). The pragmatics of indirect reports: Socio-philosophical considerations. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
  8. Cicero, M. T. (1988). In C. D. Yonge (Ed.), De inventione. London: George Bell & Sons.Google Scholar
  9. Dascal, M. (1992). On the pragmatic structure of conversation. In H. Parret & J. Verschueren (Eds.), (On) Searle on conversation (pp. 35–57). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Dascal, M. (2003). Interpretation and understanding. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Dascal, M., & Katriel, T. (1979). Digression: A study in conversational coherence. In J. Petofi (Ed.), Text vs. sentence (pp. 76–95). Hamburg: Helmut Buske Verlag.Google Scholar
  12. Freeman, J. (1988). Thinking logically, basic concepts for reasoning. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  13. Giora, R. (1985). Notes towards a theory of text coherence. Poetics Today, 6(4), 699. http://doi.org/10.2307/1771962 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Hamblin, C. L. (1970). Fallacies. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
  15. Hamblin, C. L. (1971). Mathematical models of dialogue. Theoria, 37, 130–155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hamblin, C. L. (2008). Mathematical models of dialogue. Theoria, 37(2), 130–155. http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1755-2567.1971.tb00065.x CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Harary, F. (1969). Graph theory. Menlo Park: Addison-Wesley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Heath, M. (1994). The Substructure of stasis-theory from Hermagoras to Hermogenes. The Classical Quarterly, 44(1), 114. http://doi.org/10.1017/S0009838800017250 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Hohmann, H. (1989). The dynamics of stasis: Classical rhetorical theory and modern legal argumentation. The American Journal of Jurisprudence, 34(1), 171–197. http://doi.org/10.1093/ajj/34.1.171 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Johnson, R. (1996). The rise of informal logic. Newport: Vale Press.Google Scholar
  21. Johnson, R. (2000). Manifest rationality: A pragmatic theory of argument. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  22. Johnson, R. (2003). The dialectical tier revisited. In F. van Eemeren, A. Blair, C. Willard, & F. Snoeck-Henkemans (Eds.), Anyone who has a view (pp. 41–53). Amsterdam: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Kellermann, K., & Sleight, C. (1989). Coherence: A meaningful adhesive for discourse. In J. Anderson (Ed.), Annals of the international communication association (pp. 95–129). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  24. Kennedy, G. (1963). The art of persuasion in ancient Greece. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Koszowy, M., & Walton, D. (2017). Profiles of dialogue for repairing faults in arguments from expert opinion. Logic and Logical Philosophy, 29, 79–113. http://doi.org/10.12775/LLP.2016.014 Google Scholar
  26. Krabbe, E. (1992). So what? Profiles for relevance criticism in persuasion dialogues. Argumentation, 6(2), 271–283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Krabbe, E. (2002). Profiles of dialogue as a dialectical tool. In F. Van Eemeren (Ed.), Advances in pragma-dialectics (pp. 153–167). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.Google Scholar
  28. Krabbe, E. (2013). Topical roots of formal dialectic. Argumentation, 27(1), 71–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Macagno, F. (2008). Dialectical relevance and dialogical context in Walton’s pragmatic theory. Informal Logic, 28(2), 102. http://doi.org/10.22329/il.v28i2.542 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Macagno, F. (2013). Strategies of character attack. Argumentation, 27(4), 369–401. http://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-013-9291-1 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Macagno, F. (2016). Argument relevance and structure. Assessing and developing students’ uses of evidence. International Journal of Educational Research, 79, 180–194. http://doi.org/10.1016/j.ijer.2016.07.002 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Macagno, F., & Bigi, S. (2017). Analyzing the pragmatic structure of dialogues. Discourse Studies, 19(2), 148–168. http://doi.org/10.1177/1461445617691702 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Macagno, F., & Walton, D. (2012). Character attacks as complex strategies of legal argumentation. International Journal of Law, Language & Discourse, 2(3), 59–117.Google Scholar
  34. Macagno, F., & Walton, D. (2014). Emotive language in argumentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139565776 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. McGuire, W. J. (1960). A syllogistic analysis of cognitive relationships. In M. Rosenber, C. Hovland, W. McGuire, R. Abelson, & J. Brehm (Eds.), Attitude organization and change (pp. 65–111). New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  36. McGuire, W. J. (1966). The current status of cognitive consistency theories. In S. Feldman (Ed.), Cognitive consistency: Motivational antecedents and behavioral consequents (pp. 1–26). New York: Academic.Google Scholar
  37. Morris, R. (1990). Richard Milhous Nixon: The rise of an American politician. New York: Henry Holt and Company.Google Scholar
  38. Nadeau, R. (1959). Classical systems of stases in Greek: Hermagoras to Hermogenes. Greek, Roman and Byzantine Studies, 2(1), 51–71.Google Scholar
  39. Petty, R., & Cacioppo, J. (1986). The elaboration likelihood model of persuasion. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 19, 123–205. http://doi.org/10.1016/S0065-2601 (08)60214-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Petty, R., Rucker, D., Bizer, G., & Cacioppo, J. (2004). The elaboration likelihood model of persuasion. In J. Seiter & R. Gass (Eds.), Perspectives on persuasion, social influence and compliance gaining (pp. 65–89). Boston: Allyn & Bacon.Google Scholar
  41. Poole, D., & Mackworth, A. (2010). Artificial intelligence: Foundations of computational agents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Pullman, G. (1995). Deliberative rhetoric and forensic stasis: Reconsidering the scope and function of an ancient rhetorical heuristic in the aftermath of the Thomas/Hill controversy. Rhetoric Society Quarterly, 25(1–4), 223–230. http://doi.org/10.1080/02773949509391045 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Rapanta, C., & Walton, D. (2016). The use of argument maps as an assessment tool in higher education. International Journal of Educational Research, 79, 211–221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Robinson, R. (1962). Plato’s earlier dialectic. Oxford: Oxford University Press. http://doi.org/10.1017/S003181910003638X Google Scholar
  45. Rocci, A. (2005). Are manipulative texts coherent? Manipulation, presuppositions, and (in-) congruity. In L. de Saussure & P. Schulz (Eds.), Manipulation and ideologies in the twentieth century (pp. 85–112). Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Rottenberg, A., & Winchell, D. H. (2011). The structure of argument. Boston/New York: Bedford/St. Martin’s.Google Scholar
  47. Schegloff, E. A. (1988). Presequences and indirection. Journal of Pragmatics, 12(1), 55–62. http://doi.org/10.1016/0378-2166(88)90019-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Schegloff, E. A., & Sacks, H. (1973). Opening up closings. Semiotica, 7(4), 289–327.Google Scholar
  49. Slob, W. (2002). Dialogical rhetoric: An essay on truth and normativity after postmodernism. Amsterdam: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Stump, E. (2004). Boethius’s “De topicis differentiis”. Ithaca/London: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  51. Tindale, C. W. (2015). The philosophy of argument and audience reception. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316181645 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Toulmin, S. (1958). The uses of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  53. Uckelman, S. L. (2013). Medieval disputationes de obligationibus as formal dialogue systems. Argumentation, 27(2), 143–166. http://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-012-9266-7 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Van Dijk, T. (1976). Sentence topic and discourse topic. Papers in Slavic Philology, 1, 49–61.Google Scholar
  55. Van Dijk, T. (1977). Semantic macro-structures and knowledge frames in discourse comprehension. In M. A. Just & P. Carpenter (Eds.), Cognitive processes in comprehension (pp. 3–32). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  56. van Eemeren, F. (2010). Strategic maneuvering in argumentative discourse. Extending the pragma- dialectical theory of argumentation. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. van Eemeren, F., & Grootendorst, R. (1992). Argumentation, communication, and fallacies: A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
  58. van Eemeren, F., Houtlosser, P., & Snoeck-Henkemans, F. (2015). Dialectical profiles and indicators of argumentative moves. Journal of Pragmatics, 40, 681–702. http://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-20955-5_36 Google Scholar
  59. Waller, B. (1988). Critical thinking: Consider the verdict. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  60. Walton, D. (1982). Topical relevance in argumentation. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Walton, D. (1984). Logical dialogue-games and fallacies. Lanham: University Press of America.Google Scholar
  62. Walton, D. (1989). Question-reply argumentation. Westport: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
  63. Walton, D. (1995). Argumentation schemes for presumptive reasoning. Mahwah: Routledge. http://doi.org/10.4324/9780203811160Google Scholar
  64. Walton, D. (1999). Profiles of dialogue for evaluating arguments from ignorance. Argumentation, 13(1), 53–71. http://doi.org/10.1023/A:1007738812877CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Walton, D. (2003a). Defining conditional relevance using linked arguments and argumentation schemes: a commentary on professor Callen’s article, rationality and relevancy: conditional relevancy and constrained resources. Michigan State Law Review, 4(4), 1305–1314.Google Scholar
  66. Walton, D. (2003b). Relevance in argumentation. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: Routledge. http://doi.org/10.4324/9781410609441Google Scholar
  67. Walton, D. (2013). Methods of argumentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139600187 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Walton, D. (2014). Burden of proof, Presumption and argumentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781107110311CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Walton, D. (2015). Goal-Based reasoning for argumentation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. http://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781316340554CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Walton, D., & Krabbe, E. (1995). Commitment in dialogue. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
  71. Walton, D., & Macagno, F. (2016). Profiles of dialogue for relevance. Informal Logic, 36(4), 523. http://doi.org/10.22329/il.v36i4.4586 CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing AG 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  • Fabrizio Macagno
    • 1
  • Douglas Walton
    • 2
  1. 1.Faculdade de Ciências Sociais e HumanasUniversidade Nova de LisboaLisboaPortugal
  2. 2.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of WindsorWindsorCanada

Personalised recommendations