A Closer Look at Biological Explanations

  • Marie I. Kaiser
Chapter
Part of the History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences book series (HPTL)

Abstract

Chapter 5 serves two purposes: It specifies which understanding of ‘ontic’ underlies characterizing my account of explanatory reduction as ontic and it clarifies how questions about explanation are related to questions about explanatory reduction. I show that discussions about accounts of reduction are independent from questions about explanation but that debates about explanatory reductionism, in fact, boil down to specific questions about explanation, namely, to questions about the adequacy of higher- and lower-level explanations. How one answers these questions depends on one’s stance on the pragmatics of explanation. I develop a refined version of van Fraassen’s pragmatic account of explanation that clarifies in which sense the adequacy of explanation is far from subjective or exclusively determined by pragmatic factors.

Keywords

Biological explanation Ontic account Explanatory reductionism Pragmatic account Level of explanation 

References

  1. Achinstein, P. (1983). The nature of explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Baumgartner, M., & Gebharter, A. (2015). Constitutive relevance, mutual manipulability, and fat-handedness. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
  3. Beatty, J. (1990). Evolutionary anti–reductionism: Historical considerations. Biology and Philosophy, 5, 199–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bechtel, W. (2006). Discovering cell mechanisms. The creation of modern cell biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanist alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Brigandt, I. (2013). Explanation in biology: Reduction, pluralism, and explanatory aims. Science and Education, 22(1), 69–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Byerly, H. (2003). Reductionism: Analysis and synthesis in biological explanations. The Quarterly Review of Biology, 78(3), 336–342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Coffa, J. A. (1974). Hempel’s ambiguity. Synthese, 28(2), 141–163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Craver, C. F. (2007a). Explaining the brain. Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Craver, C. F. (2007b). Constitutive explanatory relevance. Journal of Philosophical Research, 32, 3–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Craver, C. F. (2013). Functions and mechanisms: A perspectivalist view. In P. Huneman (Ed.), Functions: Selection and mechanisms (Synthese library, pp. 133–158). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Craver, C. F. (2014). The ontic conception of scientific explanation. In A. Hüttemann, M. I. Kaiser, & O. Scholz (Eds.), Explanation in the special sciences – The case of biology and history (Synthese library, pp. 27–52). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Craver, C. F., & Darden, L. (2013). In search of mechanisms. Discoveries across the life sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Darden, L. (2008). Thinking again about biological mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 75, 958–969.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Dawkins, R. (1976). The selfish gene. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Dowe, P. (1992). Process causality and asymmetry. Erkenntnis, 37(2), 179–196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Dupré, J. (1993). The disorder of things. Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Dupré, J. (2009). It is not possible to reduce biological explanations to explanations in chemistry and/ or physics. In F. J. Ayala & R. Arp (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology (pp. 32–47). Chichester: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Forge, J. (1998). Explanation and mechanism: Reflections on the ontic conception of explanation. In D. Anapolitanos, A. Baltas, & S. Tsinorema (Eds.), Philosophy and the many faces of science (pp. 76–92). Lanham: Rowman & Littelfield Publishers.Google Scholar
  21. Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 71(1), 5–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Glennan, S. S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69, 342–353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Glennan, S. S. (2010). Ephemeral mechanisms and historical explanation. Erkenntnis, 72(2), 251–266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. And other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: Free.Google Scholar
  25. Hempel, C. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1848). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15(2), 135–175.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Hitchcock, C. (1995). Discussion: Salmon on explanatory relevance. Philosophy of Science, 62, 304–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Hitchcock, C., & Woodward, J. (2003). Explanatory generalizations, part II: Plumbing explanatory depth. Noûs, 37(2), 181–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Hull, D. L., & van Regenmortel, M. H. V. (2002). Introduction. In M. H. V. van Regenmortel & D. L. Hull (Eds.), Reductionism in the biomedical sciences (pp. 1–13). London: Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Huneman, P. (2010). Topological explanations and robustness in biological sciences. Synthese, 177, 213–245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Hüttemann, A., & Love, A. C. (2011). Aspects of reductive explanation in biological science: Intrinsicality, fundamentality, and temporality. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 62(3), 519–549.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Illari, P. (2013). Mechanistic explanation: Integrating the ontic and epistemic. Erkenntnis, 78(2), 237–255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Illari, P., & Williamson, J. (2012). What is a mechanism? Thinking about mechanisms across the sciences. European Journal of Philosophy of Science, 2, 119–135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kaiser, M. I. (manuscript a). Levels as determined by parts, wholes, and kinds Google Scholar
  34. Kaiser, M. I., & Craver, C. F. (2013). Mechanisms and laws: Clarifying the debate. In H.-K. Chao, S.-T. Chen, & R. L. Millstein (Eds.), Mechanism and causality in biology and economics (pp. 125–145). Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  35. Kaiser, M. I., & Krickel, B. (forthcoming). The metaphysics of constitutive mechanistic phenomena. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
  36. Kellert, S. H., Longino, H. E., & Waters, C. K. (2006). Introduction: The pluralist stance. In S. H. Kellert, H. E. Longino, & C. K. Waters (Eds.), Scientific pluralism. Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science (pp. vii–xxix). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  37. Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 84, 507–531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Kitcher, P. (1984). 1953 an all that: A tale of two sciences. Philosophical Review, 93, 335–373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 410–506). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  40. Kitcher, P. (1999a). The hegemony of molecular biology. Biology and Philosophy, 14, 195–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Kitcher, P. (1999b). Unification as a regulative ideal. Perspectives on Science, 7(3), 337–348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Kitcher, P., & Salmon, W. C. (1987). Van Fraassen on explanation. The Journal of Philosophy, 84(6), 315–330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Leuridan, B. (2012). Three problems for the mutual manipulability account of constitutive relevance in mechanisms. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 63(2), 1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Lewis, D. (1986). Events. In D. Lewis (Ed.), Philosophical papers (Vol. II, pp. 241–269). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Love, A. C., & Hüttemann, A. (2011). Comparing part-whole reductive explanations in biology and physics. In D. Dieks, W. J. Gonzalez, S. Hartmann, T. Uebel, & M. Weber (Eds.), Explanation, prediction, and confirmation. New trends and old ones reconsidered (pp. 183–202). Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Mackie, J. L. (1974). The cement of the universe. A study of causation. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  48. McLaughlin, P. (2001). What functions explain: Functional explanation and self-reproducing systems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Mitchell, S. D. (2003). Biological complexity and integrative pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Mitchell, S. D. (2009). Unsimple truths. Science, complexity, and policy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Potochnik, A. (2009). Levels of explanation reconceived. Philosophy of Science, 77, 59–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Putnam, H. (1975). Mind, language, and reality (Philosophical papers, Vol. 2). New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Railton, P. (1981). Probability, explanation, and information. Synthese, 48, 233–256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Rosenberg, A. (2006). Darwinian reductionism. Or, how to stop worrying and love molecular biology. Cambridge: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Salmon, W. C. (1971). Statistical explanation. In W. C. Salmon (Ed.), Statistical explanation and statistical relevance (pp. 29–87). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
  56. Salmon, W. C. (1977). A third dogma of empiricism. In R. Butts & J. Hintikka (Eds.), Basic problems in methodology and linguistics (pp. 149–166). Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Salmon, W. C. (1984a). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  58. Salmon, W. C. (1984b). Scientific explanation: Three basic conceptions. PSA, 1984(2), 293–305.Google Scholar
  59. Salmon, W. C. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 3–219). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  60. Salmon, W. C. (1992). Scientific explanation. In M. H. Salmon, J. Earman, C. Glymour, J. G. Lennox, P. Machamer, J. E. McGuire, J. D. Norton, W. C. Salmon, & K. F. Schaffner (Eds.), Introduction to the philosophy of science (pp. 7–41). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
  61. Salmon, W. C. (1994). Causality without counterfactuals. Philosophy of Science, 61, 297–312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Salmon, W. C. (1997). Causality and explanation: A reply to two critiques. Philosophy of Science, 64, 461–477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Salmon, W. C. (1998). Causality and explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Sarkar, S. (1998). Genetics and reductionism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Sarkar, S. (2005). Molecular models of life. Philosophical papers on molecular biology. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  66. Sarkar, S. (2009). Ecology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2009 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/ecology/
  67. Schaffner, K. F. (1993). Discovery and explanation in biology and medicine. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  68. Skipper, R. A., & Millstein, R. L. (2005). Thinking about evolutionary mechanisms: Natural selection. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 327–347.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Sober, E. (1999). The multiple realizability argument against reductionism. Philosophy of Science, 66, 542–564.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution. The logic behind the science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Strevens, M. (2006). Scientific explanation. In D. M. Borchert (Ed.), Encyclopedia of philosophy (2nd ed.). Detroit: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  72. Strevens, M. (2008). Depth. An account of scientific explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  73. Tabery, J. G. (2004). Synthesizing activities and interactions in the concept of mechanism. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Torres, P. J. (2008). A modified conception of mechanism. Erkenntnis, 71(2), 233–251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. van Fraassen, B. C. (1977). The pragmatics of explanation. American Philosophical Quarterly, 14(2), 143–150.Google Scholar
  76. van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. van Regenmortel, M. H. V. (2004b). Biological complexity emerges from the ashes of genetic reductionism. Journal of Molecular Recognition, 17(3), 145–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Waters, C. K. (1990). Why the antireductionist consensus won’t survive the case of classical Mendelian genetics. PSA, 1990(1), 125–139.Google Scholar
  79. Waters, C. K. (2007). Causes that make a difference. The Journal of Philosophy, 104(11), 551–579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  80. Waters, C. K. (2008). Beyond theoretical reduction and layer-cake antireduction: How DNA retooled genetics and transformed biological practice. In M. Ruse (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the philosophy of biology (pp. 238–262). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  81. Wimsatt, W. C. (1980). Reductionistic research strategies and their biases in the units of selection controversy. In T. Nickles (Ed.), Scientific discovery: Case studies (pp. 213–259). Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  82. Woodward, J. (2002). What is a mechanism? A counterfactual account. Philosophy of Science, 69(3), 366–377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  83. Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  84. Woodward, J. (2010). Causation in biology: Stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biology and Philosophy, 25(3), 287–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  85. Woodward, J. (2011). Scientific explanation. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/scientific-explanation/
  86. Wright, C. D. (2012). Mechanistic explanation without the ontic conception. European Journal of Philosophy of Science, 2(3), 375–394.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  87. Wright, C. D., & Bechtel, W. (2007). Mechanisms and psychological explanation. In P. Thagard (Ed.), Philosophy of psychology and cognitive science (pp. 31–79). Amsterdam: Elsevier.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  • Marie I. Kaiser
    • 1
  1. 1.Universität zu KölnKölnGermany

Personalised recommendations