Advertisement

Arguments from Concept Possession

  • Eva Schmidt
Chapter
  • 389 Downloads
Part of the Studies in Brain and Mind book series (SIBM, volume 8)

Abstract

In this chapter, I discuss arguments for the claim that a subject can both have an experience with a certain content and not be in possession of all the concepts needed to specify this content. If she does not possess all the relevant concepts, then she cannot exercise them. So, she can undergo such an experience without being required to exercise all the concepts needed to specify its content. The argument from memory experience goes back to Martin (Philos Rev 101:745763, 1992). Since we can extract new information from memories of previous experiences when we acquire new concepts, the content of these previous experiences cannot have been fully conceptual. The argument from animal and infant perception presupposes that some subjects who lack concepts of any kind nonetheless have perceptual experiences with the same kind of content as human perception. So, the content of human perception must be nonconceptual just like the perceptual contents of these subjects. The third argument, the argument from concept acquisition (Roskies, Philos Phenomenol Res 76:633659, 2008; Noûs 44:112134, 2010), shows that we cannot explain how subjects acquire some of their first concepts, particularly perceptual-demonstrative concepts, unless we assume that experience content is nonconceptual. The question of whether a subject can have a conscious perceptual experience only if she is able to cognitively appreciate its content is a recurrent theme in the chapter; it is answered in the negative by Modest Nonconceptualism.

Keywords

Perceptual Experience Generality Constraint Perceptual State Phenomenal Concept Perceptual Sensitivity 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Bibliography

  1. Bermúdez, J. (1998). The paradox of self-consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books.Google Scholar
  2. Bermúdez, J. (2003a). Nonconceptual content: from perceptual experience to subpersonal computational states. In Y. Gunther (Ed.), Essays on nonconceptual content (pp. 183–216). Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books.Google Scholar
  3. Bermúdez, J. (2003b). Peacocke’s argument against the autonomy of nonconceptual content. In Y. Gunther (Ed.), Essays on nonconceptual content (pp. 293–308). Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books.Google Scholar
  4. Bermúdez, J. (2003c). Thinking without words. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Brewer, B. (1999). Perception and reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  6. Byrne, A. (2005). Perception and conceptual content. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 231–250). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  7. Chuard, P. (2007). The riches of experience. In R. Genarro (Ed.), Consciousness and concepts: special issue of the journal of consciousness studies (pp. 20–42). Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
  8. Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  9. Evans, J. (2008). Dual-processing accounts of reasoning, judgment, and social cognition. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 255–278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Evans, J., & Stanovich, K. (2013). Dual-process theories of higher cognition: advancing the debate. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8, 223–241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fodor, J. (1981). The present status of the innateness controversy. In J. Fodor (Ed.), Representations (pp. 257–316). Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  12. Gennaro, R. (2012). The consciousness paradox: consciousness, concepts, and higher-order thoughts. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  13. Genone, J. (n.d.). Memory and the content of experience. http://philosophy.berkeley.edu/file/233/Memory_and_the_Content_of_Experience.pdf. Accessed 28 Aug 2008.
  14. Hurley, S. (2001). Overintellectualizing the mind. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63, 423–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Lennox, J. (2015). Darwinism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition). Forthcoming. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/darwinism/.
  16. Lindsay, S. (2000). Handbook of applied dog behavior and training, vol. 1: adaptation and learning. Ames, IA: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Martin, M. (1992). Perception, concepts, and memory. The Philosophical Review, 101, 745–763.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. McDowell, J. (1982/2009c). Criteria, defeasibility and knowledge. In A. Byrne & H. Logue (Eds.), Disjunctivism: contemporary readings (pp. 75–85). Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  19. McDowell, J. (1994a). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  20. McDowell, J. (2007). What myth? Inquiry, 50, 338–351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Nida-Rümelin, M. (2010). Qualia: the knowledge argument. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2010 edition). Stanford University. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/qualia-knowledge/
  22. Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  23. Peacocke, C. (1983). Sense and content: experience, thought, and their relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  25. Peacocke, C. (2001a). Does perception have a nonconceptual content?. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 239–264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Peacocke, C. (2001b). Phenomenology and nonconceptual content. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62, 609–615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Peacocke, C. (2003). Postscript: the relations between conceptual and nonconceptual content. In Y. Gunther (Ed.), Essays on nonconceptual content (pp. 318–322). Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books.Google Scholar
  28. Peacocke, C. (2014). The mirror of the world: subjects, consciousness, and self-consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Piccinini, G. (2011). Two kinds of concept: implicit and explict. Dialogue, 50, 179–193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Priest, S. (1991). Theories of the mind. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  31. Roskies, A. (2008). A new argument for nonconceptual content. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 76, 633–659.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Roskies, A. (2010). ‘That’ response doesn’t work: against a demonstrative defense of conceptualism. Noûs, 44, 112–134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Samet, J., & Zaitchik, D. (2014). Innateness and contemporary theories of cognition. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (fall 2014 edition). Stanford University. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/innateness-cognition/
  34. Schmidt, E. (2010). The argument from animal and infant perception. Teorema, 29, 97–110.Google Scholar
  35. Speaks, J. (2005). Is there a problem about nonconceptual content?. Philosophical Review, 114, 359–398. http://www.arts.mcgill.ca/philo/speaks/papers/nonconceptual-penultimate.pdf. Accessed 20 May 2006.
  36. Spelke, E. (1990). Principles of object perception. Cognitive Science, 14, 29–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Strawson, P. (1959). Individuals: an essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  39. Tye, M. (2000). Consciousness, color, and content. Cambridge, MA: MIT.Google Scholar
  40. Tye, M. (2003a). On the virtue of being poised: reply to Seager. Philosophical Studies, 113, 275–280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Tye, M. (2003b). The Panic theory: reply to Byrne. Philosophical Studies, 113, 287–290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2015

Authors and Affiliations

  • Eva Schmidt
    • 1
  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentSaarland UniversitySaarbrückenGermany

Personalised recommendations