Virtue Epistemology Naturalized pp 207-226

Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 366)

Is There a Place for Epistemic Virtues in Theory Choice?

Chapter

Abstract

This paper challenges the appeal to theory virtues in theory choice as well as the appeal to the intellectual and moral virtues of an agent as determining unique choices between empirically equivalent theories. After arguing that theoretical virtues do not determine the choice of one theory at the expense of another theory, I argue that nor does the appeal to intellectual and moral virtues single out one agent, who defends a particular theory, and exclude another agent defending an alternative theory. I analyse Duhem’s concept of good sense and its recent interpretation in terms of virtue epistemology. I argue that the virtue epistemological interpretation does not show how good sense leads to conclusive choices and scientific progress.

References

  1. Albert, D. 1993. Quantum mechanics and experience. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Albert, D., and B. Loewer. 1988. Interpreting the many worlds interpretation. Synthese 77: 195–213.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Barrett, J. 1999. The quantum mechanics of minds and worlds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Ben-Menahem, Y. 2006. Conventionalism: From Poincaré to Quine. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bohm, D. 1952. A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of “hidden” variables, I and II. Physical Review 85: 166–193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Cushing, J. 1994. Quantum mechanics: Historical contingency and the Copenhagen hegemony. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  7. DeWitt, B. 1971. The many-universes interpretation of quantum mechanics. In Foundations of quantum mechanics, ed. B. d’Espagnat. New York: Academic Press. Reprint in The many worlds of quantum mechanics, ed. B. DeWitt and N. Graham. Princeton University Press (1973).Google Scholar
  8. Duhem, P. 1954[1906]. The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Duhem, P. 1991[1915]. German science: Some reflections on German science: German science and German virtues. Trans. John Lyon. La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
  10. Durr, D., S. Goldstein, and N. Zanghi. 1993. A global equilibrium as the foundation for quantum randomness. Foundations of Physics 23: 721–738.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Everett, H. 1957. Relative state formulation of quantum mechanics. Reviews of Modern Physics 29: 454–462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Fairweather, A. 2011. The epistemic value of good sense. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43(1): 139–146.Google Scholar
  13. Friedman, M. 2001. Dynamics of reason. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
  14. Ghirardi, G.C., A. Rimini, and T. Weber. 1986. Unified dynamics for microscopic and macroscopic systems. Physical Review 34: 470–491.Google Scholar
  15. Hull, D.L. 1988. Science as a process: An evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Ivanova, M. 2010. Pierre Duhem’s good sense as a guide to theory choice. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 41: 58–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Ivanova, M. 2011. ‘Good Sense’ in context: A response to Kidd. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 42: 610–612.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Ivanova, M., and C. Paternotte. 2013. Theory choice, good sense and social consensus. Erkenntnis 78(5): 1109–1132.Google Scholar
  19. Kitcher, P. 1993. The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Kuhn, T. 1977. Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. In The essential tension, ed. T. Kuhn, 320–353. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  21. Ladyman, J., and D. Ross (with Spurrett, D., and J. Collier). 2007. Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalised. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Leplin, J. 1997. A novel defense of scientific realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Lewis, D. 1973. Counterfactuals. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  24. McMullin, E. 2009. The virtue of a perfect theory. In The Routledge companion to philosophy of science, ed. Martin Curd and Stathis Psillos. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  25. Nolan, D. 1997. Quantitative parsimony. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48: 329–343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Psillos, S. 1999. Scientific realism – How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  27. Putnam, H. 2005. A philosopher looks at quantum mechanics (again). British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56: 615–634.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Strevens, M. 2003. The role of the priority rule in science. The Journal of Philosophy 100(2): 55–79.Google Scholar
  29. Struyve, W., and H. Westman. 2006. A new Pilot-Wave model for quantum field theory. In Quantum mechanics: Are there quantum jumps? And on the present status of quantum mechanics, AIP conference proceedings, 844, eds. A. Bassi, D. Dürr, T. Weber, and N. Zanghì, 321–339. New York: American Institute of Physics.Google Scholar
  30. Stump, D. 2007. Pierre Duhem’s virtue epistemology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 38: 149–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Stump, D. 2011. The scientist as impartial judge: Moral values in Duhem’s philosophy of science. New perspectives on Pierre Duhem’s The aim and structure of physical theory (book symposium), Metascience, vol. 20, 1–25. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  32. Swinburne, R. 1997. Simplicity as evidence of truth. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Tumulka, R. 2006. A relativistic version of the Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber model. Journal of Statistical Physics 125: 821–840.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Van Fraassen, B.C. 1980. The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Whewell, W. 1989. Theory of scientific method. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  36. Worrall, J. 1989. Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica 43(1–2): 99–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Worrall, J. 1994. How to remain (reasonably) optimistic: Scientific realism and the “Luminiferous Ether”. In PSA 1994, vol. 1, ed. M. Forbes and D. Hull. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
  38. Zagzebski, L. 2003. The search for the source of epistemic good. In Moral and epistemic virtues, ed. M. Brady and D. Pritchard, 13–27. Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of History and Philosophy of ScienceUniversity of SydneySydneyAustralia

Personalised recommendations