Implicatures as Forms of Argument

Chapter
Part of the Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology book series (PEPRPHPS, volume 1)

Abstract

In this paper, we use concepts, structure and tools from argumentation theory to show how conversational implicatures are triggered by conflicts of presumptions. Presumptive implicatures are shown to be based on defeasible forms of inference used in conditions of lack of knowledge, including analogical reasoning, inference to the best explanation, practical reasoning, appeal to pity, and argument from cause. Such inferences are modelled as communicative strategies used to fill knowledge gaps by shifting the burden of proof to provide the missing contrary evidence to the other party in a dialogue. Through a series of illustrative examples, we show how such principles of inference are based on common knowledge about the ordinary course of events shared by participants in a structured dialogue setting in which they take turns putting forward and responding to speech acts.

Keywords

Argumentation Implicatures Argumentation schemes Analogy Speech acts Pragmatics Implicit speech acts Indirect speech acts 

References

  1. Aristotle. 1984. Topics. Translated by W. A. Pickard-Cambridge. In The complete works of Aristotle, vol. I, ed. Jonathan Barnes. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Asher, Nicholas, and Alex Lascarides. 2006. Indirect speech acts. Synthese 128: 183–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bach, Kent. 1994. Meaning, speech acts, and communication. In Basic topics in the philosophy of language, ed. Robert Harnish, 3–21. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  4. Bach, Kent. 1999. The myth of conventional implicature. Linguistics and philosophy 22: 237–366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bach, Kent. 2003. Speech acts and pragmatics. In Blackwell. Guide to the philosophy of language, eds. Michael Devitt and Richard Hanley, 147–167. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  6. Ballard, Lee, Robert Conrad, and Robert Longacre. 1971. The deep and surface grammar of interclausal relations. Foundations of language 7(1): 70–118.Google Scholar
  7. Barker, Stephen. 2003. Truth and conventional implicature. Mind 112(445): 1–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Carston, Robyn. 2002. Thoughts and utterances. Malden: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Crothers, Edward. 1979. Paragraph structure inference. Norwood: Ablex.Google Scholar
  10. Davis, Wayne. 2007. How normative is implicature? Journal of pragmatics 39: 1655–1672.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Ducrot, Oswald. 1968. Le structuralisme en linguistique. In Qu’est-ce que le structuralisme?, eds. Oswald Ducrot, Todorov Tzvetan, Dan Sperber, Moustafa Safouan, and Wahl François, 13–96. Paris: Seuil.Google Scholar
  12. Ducrot, Oswald. 1972. De Saussure à la philosophie du langage, preface to John Searle, Les actes de langage, 7–34. Paris: Hermann.Google Scholar
  13. Fischer, David. 1970. Historians’ fallacies. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
  14. Goodwin, Jean. 2001. The noncooperative pragmatics of arguing. In Pragmatics in 2000: Selected papers from the 7th International Pragmatics Conference, vol. II, ed. Enikö Nemeth, 263–277. Antwerp: International Pragmatics Association.Google Scholar
  15. Grice, Paul. 1961. The causal theory of perception. Proceedings of the Aristotelian society, Supplementary 35: 121–152.Google Scholar
  16. Grice, Paul. 1975. Logic and conversation. In The logic of grammar, eds. Donald Davidson and Gilbert Harman, 64–75. Encino, California: Dickenson.Google Scholar
  17. Grice, Paul. 1989. Studies in the way of words. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Grimes, Joseph. 1975. The thread of discourse. The Hague: Mouton.Google Scholar
  19. Grosz, Barbara, and Candice Sidnert. 1986. Attention, intentions, and the structure of discourse. Computational linguistics 12(3): 175–204.Google Scholar
  20. Haspelmath, Martin. 1997. Indefinite pronouns. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Hobbs, Jerry. 1979. Coherence and coreference. Cognitive science 3: 67–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Hobbs, Jerry. 1985. On the coherence and structure of discourse. Report No. CSLI-85-37, Center for the study of language and information, Stanford University.Google Scholar
  23. Lascarides, Alex, and Nicholas Asher. 1991. Discourse relations and defeasible knowledge. In Proceedings to the 29th annual meeting of the association of computational linguistics (ACL91), Berkeley USA, 55–63. Stroudsburg, PA: Association for computational linguistics.Google Scholar
  24. Levinson, Stephen. 1995. Three levels of meaning. In Grammar and meaning, ed. Frank Palmer, 90–115. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Levinson, Stephen. 1983. Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Macagno, Fabrizio. 2008. Dialectical relevance and dialectical context in Walton’s pragmatic theory. Informal logic 28(2): 102–128.Google Scholar
  27. Macagno, Fabrizio, and Douglas Walton. 2009. Argument from analogy in law, the classical tradition, and recent theories. Philosophy and rhetoric 42(2): 154–182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Pap, Arthur. 1960. Types and meaninglessness. Mind 69(273): 41–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Perelman, Chaim, and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1951. Act and person in argument. Ethics 61(4): 251–269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Rescher, Nicholas. 1977. Dialectics: a controversy-oriented approach to the theory of knowledge. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
  31. Rigotti, Eddo. 2005. Congruity theory and argumentation. Studies in communication sciences, Special Issue: 75–96.Google Scholar
  32. Sperber, Dan, and Deidre Wilson. 1986. Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  33. Thomason, Richmond. 1990. Accommodation, meaning, and implicature: Interdisciplinary foundations for pragmatics. In Intentions in communication, ed. Philip Cohen, Jerry Morgan, and Martha Pollack, 325–363. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  34. Vanderveken, Daniel, and John Searle. 1985. Foundations of illocutionary logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Vanderveken, Daniel. 2002. Universal grammar and speech act theory. In Essays in speech act theory, ed. Daniel Vanderveken, and Susumu Kubo, 25–62. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
  36. Walton, Douglas, and Erik Krabbe. 1995. Commitment in dialogue. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
  37. Walton, Douglas. 1989. Informal logic. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Walton, Douglas. 1990. What is reasoning? What is an argument? Journal of philosophy 87: 399–419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Walton, Douglas. 1992. Slippery slope arguments. Newport News: Vale Press.Google Scholar
  40. Walton, Douglas. 1995. A pragmatic theory of fallacy. Tuscaloosa and London: The University of Alabama Press.Google Scholar
  41. Walton, Douglas. 1997. Appeal to pity. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
  42. Walton, Douglas. 1998. The new dialectic, conversational contexts of argument. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
  43. Walton, Douglas. 2002. Legal argumentation and evidence. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Walton, Douglas. 2010. Types of dialogue and burden of proof. In Computational models of argument: Proceedings of COMMA 2010, eds. Pietro Baroni, Frederico Cerutti, Massimilano Giacomin, and Guillermo Simari, 13–24. Amsterdam: IOS Press.Google Scholar
  45. Wilson, Deirdre, and Dan Sperber. 2004. Relevance theory. In Handbook of pragmatics, ed. Laurence Horn, and Gregory Ward, 607–632. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  46. Yule, George. 2008. Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.IFL, Faculdade de Ciencias Sociais e Humanas-Universidade Nova de LisboaLisboaPortugal
  2. 2.University of WindsorWindsorCanada

Personalised recommendations