Skip to main content

Collective Intentionality, Inferentialism and the Capacity for Claim-Making

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Groups, Norms and Practices

Part of the book series: Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality ((SIPS,volume 13))

Abstract

Some of our linguistic practices are special in that they involve claims about how things stand in the world. These judgments are thought to be true or false with respect to what they are about. The nature of these practices of claim-making has been studied by philosophers and psychologists alike. Furthermore, important strands in evolutionary studies have relied on both psychological and philosophical theories for addressing the question of how these practices evolved in the hominins lineage, claiming that engagement in such linguistic practices is humans’ exclusive heritage. This paper aims to show that (some of) the conceptual tools provided by collective intentionality and inferentialist theorists can productively complement each other in pursuing this theoretical endeavor, namely the elucidation of human practices of claim-making.

In particular, I argue that (i) Brandom’s inferentialist account of basic linguistic practices in interpretational terms is problematic and that these problems can be addressed via appeal to the collective intentionality theorist’s toolbox, and (ii) Inferentialists resource to linguistic norms in understanding meaning and claim-making can offer crucial tools for understanding the emergence of human specific cognitive capacities of objective judgement, tools that are needed to complement the accounts offered by collective intentionality theorists. The main aim of the paper is to provide an account of the evolution and development of human-specific abilities of claim-making which combines resources from both approaches in order to understand the nature and crucial role of shared activities in their emergence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a detailed discussion of these arguments, see Wittgenstein (1953: 186–242) and Brandom (1994: 20ff).

  2. 2.

    For a detailed argument regarding this problem in Brandom, see Satne (2017).

  3. 3.

    As we discussed above, the Content view championed by Bratman is not suited for the task at issue because its story is too cognitively-demanding. For the same reason, cognitively-demanding accounts of the ‘we’ belonging to the Subject view—such as Gilbert’s (cf. Gilbert 2014), where joint practices depend on participants’ commitments to each other—are not suited for the task.

  4. 4.

    For a detailed argument in favor of the idea that I/Thou relations are always We relations as well, see Rödl (2015) and Satne (2014a).

  5. 5.

    For a further elaboration on this point, see Hutto and Satne (2015) and Satne (2014a).

  6. 6.

    Crucial in this aspect are the folk-psychological narratives in which we are introduced through social practices of story-telling. See Hutto (2008) and Hutto and Gallagher (2008), for a detailed account of the development of practical reasoning through engagement in cultural narratives.

  7. 7.

    Accounting for the introduction of children into normative practices through social conformism has the additional advantage of avoiding giving too much weight to intricate debates about the emergence of ToM abilities and the nature of their early versions (see Low and Perner 2012). The remarks on developmental trajectories provided here fit well the specialized empirical literature on the development of capacities for understanding others in terms of reasons, placing them at the end of the developmental process, at around 3 to 4 years of age (Ibid.). In this view, infants’ success in allegedly early ToM tasks tracks not ToM abilities but precursors of them, in particular, infants’ abilities to monitor the positions of others for possibly engaging with them in basic coordinated activities (see Satne and Salice 2020 and Satne 2020).

Bibliography

  • Birch, J. (2017). The philosophy of social evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Blomberg, O. (2015). Shared goals and development. The Philosophical Quarterly, 65(258), 94–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Reasoning, representing & discursive commitment (MIE). Cambridge/London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2000). Facts, norms and normative facts: Reply to Habermas. European Journal of Philosophy, 8, 356–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2010). Conceptual content and discursive practice. Grazaer Philosophische Studien, 81(2010), 13–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (1992). Shared cooperative activity. The Philosophical Review, 1992, 327–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. (2013). Shared agency. A theory of planning together. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brownell, C. A. (2011). Early developments in joint action. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2, 193–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buttelmann, D., Daum, M., Zmyj, N., & Carpenter, M. (2013). Selective imitation of in-group over out-group members in 14-month-old infants. Child Development, 84(2), 422–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S. (2012). Interacting mindreaders. Philosophical Studies, 165(3), 841–863.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S., & Sinigaglia, C. (2014). Intention and motor representation in purposive action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1), 119–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2005). Word, niche and super-niche: How language makes minds matter more. Theoria, 20(54), 255–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2006). Language, embodiment, and the cognitive niche. Trends Cognitive Science, 10(8), 370–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2009). Natural pedagogy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(4), 148–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1973). Radical interpretation. Dialectica, 27(1), 314–328.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2014). Joint commitment: How we make the social world. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (2000). From Kant to Hegel: Robert Brandom’s pragmatic philosophy of language. European Journal of Philosophy, 8, 322–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1990). The intentionality all-stars. Philosophical Perspectives, 4, 383–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. (2008). Folk psychological narratives. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Gallagher, S. (2008). Understanding others through primary interaction and narrative practice. In J. Zlatev, T. Racine, C. Sinha, & E. Itkonen (Eds.), The shared mind: Perspectives on intersubjectivity (Converging evidence in language and communication research) (pp. 17–38). Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 521–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knoblich, G., Butterfill, S., & Sebanz, N. (2011). Psychological research on joint action: Theory and data. In B. Ross (Ed.), The psychology of learning and motivation (pp. 59–101). Burlington: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, R., & Lance, M. (2009). Yo!’ And ‘lo!’: The pragmatic topography of the space of reasons. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Low, J., & Perner, J. (2012). Implicit and explicit theory of mind: State of the art. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 30, 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malpas, J. (2011). Dialogues with Davidson: Acting, interpreting, understanding. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. (2007). The regulative dimension of folk psychology. In D. D. Hutto & M. Ratcliffe (Eds.), Folk psychology re-assessed (pp. 137–156). Dordrecht: Kluwer/Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. (2015). Mind-making practices: The social infrastructure of self-knowing agency and responsibility. Philosophical Explorations, 18(2), 259–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michael, J., Christensen, W., & Overgaard, S. (2014). Mindreading as social expertise. Synthese, 191(5), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Over, H., & Carpenter, M. (2009). Eighteen-month-old infants show increased helping following priming with affiliation. Psychological Science, 20(10), 1189–1193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2013). Intentional joint agency: Shared intention lite. Synthese, 190, 1817–1839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peregrin, J. (2012). Inferentialism and the normativity of meaning. Philosophia, 40(1), 75–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peregrin, J. (2014). Rules as the impetus of cultural evolution. Topoi, 33, 531–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rakoczy, H., Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2008). The sources of normativity: Young children’s awareness of the normative structure of games. Developmental Psychology, 44(3), 875–881.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V. (2010). Engaging minds in the first year: The developing awareness of attention and intention. In G. Bremner (Ed.), Handbook of infant development (pp. 365–393). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V. (2015). Joining intentions in infancy. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 22, 1, –2, 24-44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V., Liebal, K., Hicks, K., Jonnalagadda, S., & Chintalapuri, B. (2013a). The emergent practice of infant compliance: An exploration in two cultures. Developmental Psychology, 49(9), 1754–1762.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, V., Markova, G., & Wallot, S. (2013b). Anticipatory adjustments to being picked up in infancy. PLoS ONE, 8(6), e65289. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0065289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rochat, P. (2015). Self-conscious roots of human normativity. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(4), 741–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rödl, S. (2015). Joint action and recursive consciousness of consciousness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(4), 769–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. (2015). Articulating the world: Conceptual understanding and the scientific image. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salice, A., & Miyazono, K. (2019). Being one of us. Group identification, joint actions, and collective intentionality. Philosophical Psychology, 33(1), 42–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satne, G. (2014a). What binds us together: Normativity and the second person. Philosophical Topics, 42(1), 43–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satne, G. (2014b). Interaction and self-correction. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, 798-1–798-11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satne, G. (2016). Joint and various (collective) forms of intentionality. Journal of Social Ontology, 2(1), 105–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satne, G. (2017). Brandom and the second person. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 25(2), 189–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satne, G. (2020). Understanding others by doing things together. In Synthèse. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02692-2.

  • Satne, G., & Salice, A. (2020). Shared intentionality and the cooperative evolutionary hypothesis. In A. Fiebich (Ed.), Minimal cooperation and shared agency, 71–92. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, H.-B. (2009). Plural action: Essays in philosophy and social science. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schweikard, D. & Schmid, H.-B. (2013). Collective intentionality. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2013 edition).

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1990). Collective intentions and actions. In P. Cohen, J. Morgan, & M. Pollack (Eds.), Intentions in communication (pp. 401–415). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1954). Some reflections on language games. Philosophy of Science, 21(3), 204–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1, 253–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2012). The evolved apprentice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tennie, C., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2009). Ratcheting up the ratchet: On the evolution of cumulative culture. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 364(1528), 2405–2415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tennie, C., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2012). Untrained chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes schweinfurthii) fail to imitate novel actions. PLoS One, 7(8), e41548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, D. (2005). Let’s pretend! Children and joint action. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 35(1), 75–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, D., & Dale, R. (2012). Naturalizing joint action: A process-based approach. Philosophical Psychology, 25(3), 385–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2008). Origins of human communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2014). A natural history of human thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2016). Response to commentators. Journal of Social Ontology, 2(1), 117–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., & Rakoczy, H. (2003). What makes human cognition unique? From individual to shared to collective intentionality. Mind & Language, 18(2), 121–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., & Moll, H. (2005). Understanding and sharing intentions: The origins of cultural cognition. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28(5), 675–691.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warneken, F., & Tomasello, M. (2007). Helping and cooperation at 14 months of age. Infancy, 11(3), 271–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D., & Satne, G. (2015). Varieties of shared intentionality: Tomasello and classical phenomenology. In J. Bell, A. Cutrofello, & P. Livingston (Eds.), Beyond the analitic-continental divide: Pluralist philosophy in the twenty-first century (pp. 305–325). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zawidzki, T. (2013). Mindshaping. A new framework for understanding human social cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Glenda Satne .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Satne, G. (2021). Collective Intentionality, Inferentialism and the Capacity for Claim-Making. In: Koreň, L., Schmid, H.B., Stovall, P., Townsend, L. (eds) Groups, Norms and Practices. Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality, vol 13. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-49590-9_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics