Advertisement

Realism and the Advancement of Knowledge

  • Paul Needham
Chapter
  • 16 Downloads
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 423)

Abstract

The chapter advocates a view of the progress of science as the acquisition of knowledge—knowledge of the world as the literal understanding (with some qualification) of contemporary scientific theory would have it. This is challenged by antirealists, who accept this claim only for knowledge of what they count as observable, which they distinguish from the theoretical representation afforded by science and which they maintain we are not justified in holding as a literally true representation of how the world really is. The antirealist challenge is met by a moderate realism, which rebuts the anitirealist arguments of Laudan’s pessimistic induction, Kuhn’s argument from the putative incommensurability of successive theories and Bas van Fraassen’s argument from the so-called underdetermination of theory, but without resorting to the miracle argument or the strategy of inference to the best explanation on which it relies, which are also rejected. It is not necessary to accept the more extreme claims about preservation of reference throughout scientific change in order to rebut antirealism, and Putnam’s thesis of the preservation of the extension of “water”, the idea that Dalton’s atoms are the same things as the atoms of modern science, Psillos’s device of saving the reference of abandoned terms and the claims of structural realism are all discussed and rejected. In the course of this discussion I try to steer a middle path of a moderate realism that acknowledges the force of the natural view that science is to be taken literally, accommodating change over the course of history in the spirit of Duhem’s continuity thesis and recognising that there are aspects of theory that scientists themselves don’t take literally.

References

  1. Akeroyd, M. (2003). The Lavoisier-Kirwan debate and approaches to the evaluation of theories. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 988, 293–301.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Ariew, R. (1984). The Duhem thesis. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 35, 313–325.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Aristotle (1984). The complete works of Aristotle (Vol. 1). Barnes, J. (Ed.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Asay, J. (2018). Realism and theories of truth. In J. Saatsi (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of scientific realism (pp. 383–393). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  5. Bird, A. (2007). What is scientific progress? Noûs, 41, 64–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bohr, N. (1965). The structure of the atom. In Nobel lectures, physics 1922–1941 (pp. 7–43). Amsterdam: Elsevier Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  7. Bogen, J., & Woodward, J. (1988). Saving the phenomena. Philosophical Review, 97, 303–352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Bukulich, A. (2008). Reexamining the quantum-classical relation: Beyond reductionism and pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Chakravartty, A. (2008). What you don’t know can’t hurt you: Realism and the unconceived. Philosophical Studies, 137, 149–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Chang, H. (2003). Preservative realism and its discontents: Revisiting caloric. Philosophy of Science, 70, 902–912.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Coulson, C. A. (1955). The contributions of wave mechanics to chemistry. Journal of the Chemical Society, 2069–2084.Google Scholar
  12. Davy, H. (1840). Works of Sir Humphrey Davy (Vol. VII). London: Smith, Elder and Co.Google Scholar
  13. Dellsén, F. (2016). Scientific progress: Knowledge versus understanding. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 56, 72–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Dellsén, F. (2018). Scientific progress, understanding, and knowledge: Reply to Park. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 49(3), 451–459.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Dorling, J. (1973). Demonstrative induction: Its significant role in the history of physics. Philosophy of Science, 40, 360–372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Duhem, P. (1895). Les Théories de la Chaleur. Revue des Deux Mondes, 129, 869–901; 130, 380–415, 851–68. Translated as “Theories of Heat” in Duhem (2002).Google Scholar
  17. Duhem, P. (1902). Le mixte et la combinaison chimique: Essai sur l’évolution d’une idée. Paris: C. Naud. Translated in Duhem (2002).Google Scholar
  18. Duhem, P. (1954). The aim and structure of physical theories (trans. of 2nd. ed. of Duhem (1906b) by Philip Wiener). New Jersey: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Earley, J. E. (2005). Why there is no salt in the sea. Foundations of Chemistry, 7, 85–102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Einstein, A. (1905 [1956]). Über die von der molekularkinetischen Theorie der Wärme geforderte Bewegung von in ruhenden Flüssigkeiten suspendierten Teilchen. Annalen der Physik, 17(8), 549–560; translated in Investigations on the theory of the Brownian movement. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
  21. Feynman, R. P. (1939). Forces in molecules. Physical Review, 56, 340–343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Galileo, G. (1632 [1967]). Dialogues concerning the two chief world systems (trans: Drake, S.). Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  23. Giedymin, J. (1982). Science and convention. Oxford: Pergamon Press.Google Scholar
  24. Harman, G. (1965). Inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Review, 74, 88–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Heitler, W., & London, F. (1927). Wechselwirkung neutraler Atome und homöopolare Bindung nach der Quantenmechanik. Zeitschrift für Physik, 44, 455–472. Trans. in Hettema, H. (2000). Quantum chemistry: Classic scientific papers (pp. 140–55). Singapore: World Scientific.Google Scholar
  26. Hunt, B. J. (1991). The Maxwellians. New York: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Iliopoulos, J. (2017). The origin of mass: Elementary particles and fundamental symmetries. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Klein, U. (1994). Origin of the concept of chemical compound. Science in Context, 7, 163–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Knight, D. (1978). The transcendental part of chemistry. Folkestone: Dawson.Google Scholar
  30. Kuhn, T. S. (1957). The Copernican revolution. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Kutzelnigg, W. (1996). Friedrich Hund and chemistry. Angewandte Chemie, International Edition in English, 35, 573–586.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Ladyman, J. (2000). What’s really wrong with constructive empiricism? van Fraassen and the Metaphysics of Modality. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51, 837–856.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Ladyman, J. (2004). Constructive empiricism and modal metaphysics: A reply to Monton and van Fraassen. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55, 755–765.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Ladyman, J. (2009). Structural realism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2009 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/structural-realism/
  35. Laudan, L. (1981 [1984]). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–49. Reprinted in J. Leplin (Ed.), Scientific realism (pp. 218–249). Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  36. Lavoisier, A. (1789 [1965]). Traité Élémentaire de Chimie. Paris. Trans. by Robert Kerr (1790) as Elements of chemistry. New York: Dover. Reprint.Google Scholar
  37. Levy, A. (2015). Modeling without models. Philosophical Studies, 172(3), 781–798.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Lewis, G. N. (1916). The atom and the molecule. Journal of the American Chemical Society, 38, 762–785.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Lewis, G. N. (1917). The static atom. Science, 46, 297–302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Lewis, G. N. (1923). Valence and the structure of atoms and molecules. New York: Chemical Catalog Co.; Reprinted in 1966 by Dover, New York.Google Scholar
  41. Lubbe, S. C. C. van der, & Fonseca Guerra, C. (2019). The nature of hydrogen bonds: A delineation of the role of different energy components on hydrogen bond strengths and lengths. Chemistry—An Asian Journal, 14(16), 2760–2769.Google Scholar
  42. Lubbe, S. C. C. van der, Zaccaria, F., Sun, X., & Fonseca Guerra, C. (2019). Secondary electrostatic interaction model revised: Prediction comes mainly from measuring charge accumulation in hydrogen-bonded monomers. Journal of the American Chemical Society, 141, 4878–4885.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Mizrahi, M. (2013). The pessimistic induction: A bad argument gone too far. Synthese, 190, 3209–3226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Mizrahi, M. (2018). The ‘positive argument’ for constructive empiricism and inference to the best explanation. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 49(3), 461–466.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Mulliken, R. S. (1931). Bonding power of electrons and theory of valence. Chemical Reviews, 9, 347–388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Needham, P. (2004). When did atoms begin to do any explanatory work in chemistry? International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 8, 199–219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Needham, P. (2008b). Resisting chemical atomism: Duhem’s argument. Philosophy of Science, 75, 921–931.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Needham, P. (2009a). An Aristotelian theory of chemical substance. Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy, 12, 149–164.Google Scholar
  49. Needham, P. (2009b). Reduction and emergence: A critique of Kim. Philosophical Studies, 146, 93–116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Needham, P. (2010). Substance and time. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61(2010), 485–512.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Needham, P. (2012). Compounds and Mixtures. In R. F. Hendry, P. Needham, & A. J. Woody (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science (Vol. 6, Philosophy of chemistry, pp. 271–290). Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  52. Needham, P. (2013). Hydrogen bonding: Homing in on a tricky chemical concept. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 44, 51–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Needham, P. (2014). The source of chemical bonding. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 45C, 1–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Needham, P. (2018). Scientific realism and chemistry. In J. Saatsi (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of scientific realism (pp. 345–356). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  55. Norton, J. (1993). The determination of theory by evidence: The case for quantum discontinuity, 1900–1915. Synthese, 97, 1–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Norton, J. (1994). Science and certainty. Synthese, 99, 3–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Norton, J. (2003). A material theory of induction. Philosophy of Science, 70, 647–670.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Norton, J. (2006). The formal equivalence of grue and green and how it undoes the new riddle of induction. Synthese, 150, 185–207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Norton, J. (2010). There are no universal rules for induction. Philosophy of Science, 77, 765–777.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Norton, J. (2011). History of science and the material theory of induction: Einstein’s quanta, mercury’s perihelion. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 1, 3–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Norton, J. (2014). A material dissolution of the problem of induction. Synthese, 191, 671–690.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Norton, J. (2015). Replicability of experiment. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science, 30(2), 229–248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Nye, M. J. (1993). From chemical philosophy to theoretical chemistry: Dynamics of matter and dynamics of disciplines 1800–1950. Berkeley: California University Press.Google Scholar
  64. Ohanian, H. C. (1988). Classical electrodynamics. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.Google Scholar
  65. Papineau, D. (1996). Editor’s “Introduction”. In The philosophy of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  66. Park, S. (2017). Does scientific progress consist in increasing knowledge or understanding? Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 48(4), 569–579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Partington, J. R. (1962). A history of chemistry (Vol. 3). London: Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Poincaré, H. (1902 [1952]). La Science et l’Hypothèse. Flammarion, 1902; trans. Science and hypothesis. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
  69. Price, D. J. De S. (1959). Contra Copernicus: A critical re-estimation of the mathematical planetary theory of Ptolemy, Copernicus and Kepler. In M. Claggett (Ed.), Critical problems in the history of science. Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
  70. Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  71. Psillos, S. (2018). The realist turn in the philosophy of science. In J. Saatsi (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of scientific realism (pp. 20–34). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  72. Putnam, H. (1975a). Mathematics, matter and method (Philosophical papers, Vol. 1). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  73. Putnam, H. (1975b). Mind, language and reality (Philosophical papers, Vol. 2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Quine, W. V. (1951). Two dogmas of empiricism. Philosophical Review, 60; Reprinted with changes in From a logical point of view (rev ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1961.Google Scholar
  75. Quine, W. V. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
  76. Quine, W. V. (1975). On empirically equivalent systems of the world. Erkenntnis, 9, 313–328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. Quine, W. V. (1976). A comment on Grünbaum’s claim. In S. Harding (Ed.), Can theories be refuted?. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  78. Raftopoulos, A. (1999). Newton’s experimental proofs as eliminative reasoning. Erkenntnis, 50(1), 95–125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. Schupbach, J. N. (2017). Inference to the best explanation, cleaned up and made respectable. In K. McCain & T. Poston (Eds.), Best explanations (pp. 39–61). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  80. Sengers, J. L. (2002). How fluids unmix: Discoveries by the school of Van der Waals and Kamerlingh Onnes. Amsterdam: Koninklijke Nederlandse Adakamie van Wetenschappen.Google Scholar
  81. Stanford, P. K. (2018). Unconceived alternatives and the strategy of historical ostension. In J. Saatsi (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of scientific realism (pp. 212–224). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  82. van Fraassen, B. (1980). The image of science. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  83. van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  84. Weintraub, R. (2017). Scepticism about inference to the best explanation. In K. McCain & T. Poston (Eds.), Best explanations (pp. 170–202). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  85. Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 639–659.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  86. Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica, 43, 99–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  • Paul Needham
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of StockholmStockholmSweden

Personalised recommendations