Advertisement

Darwin, the Modern Synthesis, and a New Biology

  • John Torday
  • William Miller Jr.
Chapter
  • 50 Downloads

Abstract

Any attempt to provide a coherent alternative evolutionary narrative to standard Darwinian tenets should offer a brief overview of the progression of scholarly thought about evolutionary mechanisms. All narratives focus on Charles Darwin's seminal “On the Origin of Species” (Darwin 1859). When Darwin offered that influential work in 1859, he was unaware of the existence of genes. He was a naturalist with a gift for scrupulous observation. Based upon his studies, he proposed the major dictums that have since guided evolutionary thoughts. He offered two linked primary arguments. Evolution proceeded by a process of natural selection through the gradual modification of inherited variations. Notably, the concept of natural selection was not original to Darwin. In 1831, a Scottish horticulturalist, Patrick Matthew had proposed a theory of natural selection, and Darwin was acquainted with his work (Rampino 2010). Another English naturalist and explorer, Alfred Russel Wallace was in communication with Darwin prior to his publication of On the Origin of Species. His correspondence with Darwin had outlined a deliberate mechanism for evolution that incorporated the concept of natural selection. However, it was Darwin's considerable reputation in the scientific community that gave an effective voice to this explosively controversial theory and energized its broader intellectual scrutiny. In this manner, Darwin was substantially adding to an already existing and lively debate. The nineteenth century French naturalist, Jean-Baptiste Lamarck also believed in evolution, and argued that it proceeded through natural laws. He and his many advocates proposed that individuals could inherit characteristics from their ancestors based on the patterns of use of the various faculties (Bowler 2003). For example, the long necks of giraffes were thought to be due to the stretching of their necks to reach high branches of trees. Darwin did not specifically disagree. He had espoused a variant of Lamarckism that he termed “pangenesis” in his 1868 text, Variation in Plants and Animals Under Domestication. A German biologist, Ernst Haeckel, added his own form of support in the 1870s with his well-known “ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny” hypothesis (Bowler 2003). He proposed that the stages of development of an embryo conformed to successive stages of its ancestral evolutionary development. Further reinforcement for this position emerged in the latter part of the nineteenth century through Wilhelm Haeckel's proposal of “orthogenesis.” Strenuously promoted by the German zoologist Theodore Eimer, orthogenesis was the process by which an organism directed toward a determined course by internal forces. In that circumstance, variation is not random, and selection need not be preponderant since a species is carried forward automatically by inner dynamics (Fox and Wolf 2006). Although the concept that one biological mechanism builds upon another in a non-random manner fell into substantial disfavor in the twentieth century, its basic validity has been resurrected on the basis of modern research in cell–cell signaling (Torday and Miller Jr 2017). It can be seen, then, that evolution has been the subject of intense and longstanding debate. Vigorous controversies remain about the primacy of natural selection, the role of acquired characteristics, sources of variation, and whether or not the evolution is random.

Keywords

Orthogenesis Gradualism Modern Synthesis Neutral theory Endosymbiosis Extended Evolutionary Synthesis Self-awareness Self-organization Environmental stress Cognition-based evolution Natural genetic engineering Neo-Darwinism 

References

  1. Baluška F, Levin M (2016) On having no head: cognition throughout biological systems. Front Psych 7:902Google Scholar
  2. Baluška F, Miller WB Jr (2018) Senomic view of the cell: senome versus genome. Commun Integr Biol 11(3):1–9CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  3. Ben-Jacob E (2009) Learning from bacteria about natural information processing. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1178:78–90CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  4. Ben-Jacob E, Finkelshtein A, Ariel G, Ingham C (2016) Multispecies swarms of social microorganisms as moving ecosystems. Trends Microbiol 24:257–269CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bowler PJ (2003) Evolution: the history of an idea. University of California Press, BerkeleyGoogle Scholar
  6. Caporale LH (2003) Darwin in the genome: molecular strategies in biological evolution. McGraw-Hill, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  7. Caporale LH, Doyle J (2013) In Darwinian evolution, feedback from natural selection leads to biased mutations. Ann N Y Acad Sci 1305:18–28Google Scholar
  8. Carroll SB (2005a) Endless forms most beautiful. W.W. Norton and Co., New YorkGoogle Scholar
  9. Crombach A, Hogeweg P (2008) Evolution of evolvability in gene regulatory networks. PLoS Comput Biol 4:e1000112CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  10. Darwin C (1859) On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life. John Murray, LondonGoogle Scholar
  11. Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  12. De Loof A (2015a) How to deduce and teach the logical and unambiguous answer, namely L = ∑C, to “What is Life?” using the principles of communication? Commun Integr Biol 8:1–11Google Scholar
  13. De Loof A (2015b) From Darwin’s on the origin of species by means of natural selection to the evolution of life with communication activity as its very essence and driving force (= mega-evolution). Funct Genomics 3:153–187Google Scholar
  14. De Queiroz K (2005) Ernst Mayr and the modern concept of species. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 102:6600–6607CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  15. Doolittle WF, Sapienza C (1980) Selfish genes, the phenotype paradigm and genome evolution. Nature 284:601–603CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Fodor J, Piattelli-Palmarini M (2010) What Darwin got wrong. Picador, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  17. Ford BJ (2004) Are cells ingenious? Microscope 52:135–144Google Scholar
  18. Ford BJ (2009) On intelligence in cells: the case for whole cell biology. Interdiscip Sci Rev 34:350–365CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Ford BJ (2017) Cellular intelligence: microphenomenology and the realities of being. Prog Biophys Mol Biol 131:273–287CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Fox CW, Wolf P (2006) Evolutionary genetics. Concepts and case studies. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  21. Gilbert SF (2014) Symbiosis as the way of eukaryotic life: the dependent co-origination of the body. J Biosci 39:201–209CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Gould SJ (1977) Ontogeny and Phylogeny. Belknap Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  23. Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (1999) Epigenetic inheritance and evolution: the Lamarckian dimension. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  24. Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2008) The epigenome in evolution: beyond the modern synthesis. Vosgis Herald 12:242–254Google Scholar
  25. Kimura M (1968) Evolutionary rate at the molecular level. Nature 217:624–626CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  26. Kimura M (1991) Recent development of the neutral theory viewed from the Wrightian tradition of theoretical population genetics. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 88:5969–5973CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  27. Koonin EV (2009) Darwinian evolution in the light of genomics. Nucleic Acids Res 37:1011–1034CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  28. Laland K, Uller T, Feldman M, Sterelny K, Müller GB, Moczek A, Jablonka E, Odling-Smee J, Wray GA, Hoekstra HE, Futuyma DJ, Lenski RE, Mackay TF, Schluter D, Strassmann JE (2014) Does evolutionary theory need a rethink? Nature 514:161–164CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Laland KN, Uller T, Feldman MW, Sterelny K, Müller GB, Moczek A, Jablonka E, Odling-Smee J (2015) The extended evolutionary synthesis: its structure, assumptions and predictions. Proc R Soc B 282:20151019CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Lyon P (2015) The cognitive cell: bacterial behavior reconsidered. Front Microbiol 6:264CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  31. Margulis L (1993) Symbiosis in cell evolution: microbial communities in the archaean and proterozoic eras. W.H. Freeman, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  32. Margulis L, Dolan MF, Guerrero R (2000) The chimeric eukaryote: origin of the nucleus from the karyomastigont in a mitochondriate protists. Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 97:6954–6959CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  33. McClintock B (1987) Discovery and characterization of transposable elements: the collected papers of Barbara McClintock. Garland, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  34. Miller WB (2013) The microcosm within: evolution and extinction in the hologenome. Universal Publishers, Boca RatonGoogle Scholar
  35. Miller WB (2016a) Cognition, information fields and hologenomic entanglement: evolution in light and shadow. Biology (Basel) 5(2):21Google Scholar
  36. Miller WB (2017) Biological information systems: evolution as cognition-based information management. Prog Biophys Mol Biol 134:1–36Google Scholar
  37. Miller WB Jr, Torday JS (2018) Four domains: the fundamental unicell and Post-Darwinian cognition-based evolution. Prog Biophys Mol Biol 140:49–73CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  38. Miller WB Jr, Torday JS (2019) Reappraising the exteriorization of the mammalian testes through evolutionary physiology. Commun Integr Biol 12:38–54CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  39. Miller WB, Torday JS (2017) A systematic approach to cancer: evolution beyond selection. Clin Transl Med 3:2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Mullock BM, Luzio JP (2005) Theory of organelle biogenesis. In: The biogenesis of cellular organelles. Springer, BostonGoogle Scholar
  41. Noble D (2010) Biophysics and systems biology. Philos Trans R Soc A 368:1125–1139CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Noble D (2015) Evolution beyond Darwinism: a new conceptual framework. J Exp Biol 218:7–13CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  43. Odling-Smee FJ, Laland KN, Feldman MW (2003) Niche construction: the neglected process in evolution. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  44. Ohta T, Gillespie JH (1996) Development of neutral and nearly neutral theories. Theor Popul Biol 49:128–142CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  45. Orgel LE, Crick FH (1980) Selfish DNA: the ultimate parasite. Nature 284:604–607CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Pigliucci M (2007) Do we need an extended evolutionary synthesis. Evolution 61:2743–2749CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Provine WB (1971) The origins of theoretical population genetics. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  48. Radman M, Matic I, Taddei F (1999) Evolution of evolvability. Ann N Y Acad Sci 870:146–155CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  49. Rampino MR (2010) Darwin’s error? Patrick Matthew and the catastrophic nature of the geologic record. Hist Biol 23:227–330CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Rose MR, Oakley TH (2007) The new biology: beyond the modern synthesis. Biol Direct 2:30–47CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  51. Rosenberg E, Sharon G, Zilber-Rosenberg I (2009) The hologenome theory of evolution contains Lamarckian aspects within a Darwinian framework. Environ Microbiol 11:2959–2962Google Scholar
  52. Ryan FP (2009) Virolution. Harper Collins Publishers, LondonGoogle Scholar
  53. Ryan F (2010) You are half virus. New Scientist 205:32–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Rybnikov SR, Frenkel ZM, Kirzhner VM, Korol AB (2015) Complex dynamics of multilocus genetic systems: a revisit of earlier findings in relation to ecosystem evolution. Bot Pacifica 4:13–17Google Scholar
  55. Shapiro JA (2011) Evolution: a view from the 21st century. FT Press, Upper Saddle RiverGoogle Scholar
  56. Shapiro JA (2017a) Biological action in read–write genome evolution. Interface Focus 7:20160115CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  57. Torday JS (2013) Evolutionary biology redux. Perspect Biol Med 56:455–484Google Scholar
  58. Torday JS (2015a) The cell as the mechanistic basis for evolution. WIREs Syst Biol Med 7:275–284Google Scholar
  59. Torday JS (2015b) A central theory of biology. Med Hypotheses 85:49–57PubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  60. Torday JS (2019) The singularity of nature. Prog Biophys Mol Biol 142:23–31Google Scholar
  61. Torday JS, Miller WB Jr (2017) The resolution of ambiguity as the basis for life: a cellular bridge between Western reductionism and Eastern holism. Prog Biophys Mol Biol 131:288–297CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  62. Torday JS, Rehan VK (2009) Lung evolution as a cipher for physiology. Physiol Genomics 38:1–6PubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  63. Witzany G (2010) Biocommunication and natural genome editing. World J Biol Chem 1:348CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  64. Woese CR, Goldenfeld N (2009) How the microbial world saved evolution from the scylla of molecular biology and the charybdis of the modern synthesis. Microbiol Mol Biol Rev 73:14–21CrossRefPubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  65. Zimorski V, Ku C, Martin WF, Gould SB (2014) Endosymbiotic theory for organelle origins. Curr Opin Microbiol 22:38–48CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  • John Torday
    • 1
  • William Miller Jr.
    • 2
  1. 1.Deptartment of Pediatrics, Obstetrics and GynecologyHarbor–UCLA Medical CenterTorranceUSA
  2. 2.Physician/Independent researcherBanner Health/J.C.Lincoln Health SystemsParadise ValleyUSA

Personalised recommendations