Advertisement

Disability Justice in Practice: Instituting a New Public Culture of Obligations

  • Oche OnaziEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice book series (IUSGENT, volume 78)

Abstract

This chapter considers how the African legal philosophy of disability justice can be translated into practice in contributing to the improvement of the community experience for people with disabilities. It does so by providing the outlines of a new public moral culture of stringent ethical and moral horizontal obligations owed to people with disabilities by people without disabilities. It argues that a new public moral culture of obligations is contingent on a moral and political educational agenda capable of nurturing special obligations owed to people with disabilities and other vulnerable citizens. An essential part of this reform agenda is predicated on moral and political citizenship education supported by a hypothecated tax scheme, both of which would provide a vehicle to concretise the kind of ethical and moral obligations foundational to African legal philosophy. It is argued that this would underscore the obligations incumbent on people without disabilities to treat others with compassion, especially people with disabilities, as a basic requirement of morality and justice that binds members of any political community.

Keywords

Obligations Disability justice Civic and citizenship education Disability simulations Tax Hypothecation 

References

  1. Africa Tax Justice Network (2010) Building a fair, transparent and inclusive tax system in Sierra Leone: Sierra Leone Report. Tax Justice Network Africa, KenyaGoogle Scholar
  2. African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights (1980) (The Banjul Charter)Google Scholar
  3. Ahiauzu N (2006) Ubuntu and the obligation to obey the law. Cambr Law Rev 37(17):17–36Google Scholar
  4. Alston P, Goodman R (2013) International human rights. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  5. Bamford D (2015) Ethical taxation: progressivity, efficiency and hourly averaging. In: Gaisbauer H, et al (eds) Philosophical explorations of justice and taxation, Ius Gentium: Comparative Perspectives on Law and Justice. Dordrecht: Springer, pp 135–150Google Scholar
  6. Bankowski Z (2001) Living lawfully: law in love and law in love. Springer, DordrechtCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Barrett J (2012) Democratic discourse, taxation and hypothecation. J Aust Tax 89(14):89–117Google Scholar
  8. Bodea C, Lebass A (2013) The origins of social contract: attitudes towards taxation in urban Nigeria. Centre for the Studies of African Economies, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  9. Boot E (2017) Human duties and the limits of human rights discourse. Studies in global justice. Springer International Publishing, SwitzerlandCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Brid-Pollan J (2017) The philosophical foundations of wealth transfer taxation. In: Bhandari M (ed) Philosophical foundations of tax law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 217–231CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Buchanan J (1963) The economics of earmarked taxes. J Polit Econ 71(5):457–469CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Bujo B (2001) Foundations of an African ethic: beyond the universal claims of western morality. Crossroad Publishing Company, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  13. Chilemba E (2014) Malawi. Afr Disability Rights Yearb 2:207–226Google Scholar
  14. Cornell D (2014) Law and revolution in South Africa: Ubuntu, dignity, and the struggle for constitutional transformation. Fordham University Press, New YorkCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Cornell D, Muvungua N (2012) Ubuntu and the law: African ideals and postaparthied jurisprudence. Fordham University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  16. Dodsworth C (2007) A theory of obligation. Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, University of Michigan. MichiganGoogle Scholar
  17. Douglas S (2015) Ubuntu versus Ubuntu: finding a philosophy of justice through obligation. Law Crit 26:305–312CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Duff D (2017) Tax policy and the virtuous sovereign: Dworkinian equality and redistributive taxation. In: Bhandari M (ed) Philosophical foundation of tax law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 167–182CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Eide A, Ingstad B (2011) Disability and poverty: a global challenge. Bristol University Press, BristolCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Eslin P, Horsthemke K (2004) Can Ubuntu provide a model for citizenship education in African democracies? Comparative Education 40(4):545–558CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Etieyibo E (2017) Moral education, Ubuntu and Ubuntu-inspired communities. South Afr J Philos 36(3):311–325CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Ferrante C, Eduardo J (2016) Begging and disability: a pragmatic way to earn one’s living. In: Grech S, Soldatic K (eds) Disability in the global south: the critical handbook. Springer Nature, Switzerland, pp 151–166CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Flower A et al (2007) Meta-analysis of disability simulation research. Remedial Spec Educ 28(2):72–79CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. French S (1992) Simulation exercises in disability awareness training: a critique. Disabil, Handicap Soc 7(3):257–266CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Gardner L (2012) Taxing colonial Africa: the political economy of British imperialism. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Goodfellow T, Owen O (2018) Taxation, property rights and the social contract in Lagos. Int Cent Tax, Bright 73:1–36Google Scholar
  27. Goodley D, Swartz L (2016) The place of disability. In: Grech S, Soldatic K (eds) Disability in the global south: the critical handbook. Springer Nature, Switzerland, pp 69–83CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Grobbelaar-du Plessis I (2013) South Africa. Afr Disability Rights Yearb 1:307–340Google Scholar
  29. Groce N et al (2011) Disability and poverty: the need for a more nuanced understanding of implications for development policy and practice. Third World Quarterly 32(8):1493–1513CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Gyamfi E (2013) Ghana Afr Disabil Rights Yearb 1:221–243Google Scholar
  31. Gyekye K (1997) Tradition and modernity: philosophical reflections on the African person. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Halliday D (2015) Egalitarianism and consumption tax. In: Gaisbauer H et al (eds) Philosophical explorations of justice and taxation. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 119–133Google Scholar
  33. Hanass-Hancock J, Mitra S (2016) Livelihoods and disability: the complexities of work in the Global South. In: Grech S, Soldatic K (eds) Disability in the global south: the critical handbook. Springer Nature, Switzerland, pp 133–149CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Heyns C (2001) The African human rights systems: in need for reform. Afr Human Rights Law J 1:155–174Google Scholar
  35. Hobbes T (2016) [1651] Leviathan. In: Brookes C (ed) Penguin Classics, Chapter XXX.Google Scholar
  36. Holmes S, Sunstein C (2000) The cost of rights: why liberty depends on taxes. W.W. Norton and Company, Cambridge MassachusettsGoogle Scholar
  37. Honore T (1993) The dependence of morality on law. Oxf J Leg Stud 13(1):1–17CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. International Disability Alliance in partnership with the International Disability and Development Consortium, UNICEF and the UN Partnership to promote the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (2014) Nairobi Declaration for Inclusive post 2015 development agenda and UN CRPD in Africa (Nairobi Declaration). Pan-African disabled persons organisations, KenyaGoogle Scholar
  39. International Labour Organization (2015) Five facts about informal economy in Africa. International Labour Organization, SwitzerlandGoogle Scholar
  40. James K, Emerton P (2017) The justice of the tax base and the case for income tax. In: Bandari M (ed) Philosophical foundation of tax law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 125–166Google Scholar
  41. Jolley E et al (2017) Education and social inclusion of people with disabilities in five countries in West Africa: a literature review. Disabil Rehabil: 1–9Google Scholar
  42. Kamundia E (2014) Kenya. Afr Disability Rights Yearb 2:185–205Google Scholar
  43. Kiger G (1992) Disability simulations: Logical, methodological and ethical issues. Disability, Handicap Soc 7(1):71–78CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Ladd J (1998) The idea of community, an ethical exploration, part II: community as a system of social and moral interrelationships. J Value Inq 32:153–174CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Landes X (2015) Why taxing consumption? In: Gaisbauer HP et al (eds) Philosophical explorations of justice and taxation. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 101–117Google Scholar
  46. Little J (1988) Simone Weil: waiting on truth, Berg women’s series. St Martin’s Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  47. Locke J 2018 [1690] The second treatise of government. In: Macpherson CB, (ed) Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co. LtdGoogle Scholar
  48. Mathews D, Veitch S (2018) Law, community and obligation. Routledge, Abingdon, OxonCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. McGee R (ed) (2012) The ethics of tax evasion: perspectives in theory and practice. Springer, DordrechtGoogle Scholar
  50. Menendez A (2001) Justifying taxes: some elements for a general theory of democratic tax law. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht, p 117CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Menkiti I (1984) Person and community in African traditional thought. In: Wright R (ed) African philosophy: an introduction. University Press of America, New York, pp 171–181Google Scholar
  52. Metz T (2007) Toward an African moral theory. J Polit Philos 15(3):321–341CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Metz T (2015) An African egalitarianism: Bringing community to bear on equality. In: Hull G (ed) The equal society: essays on equality in theory and practice. Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham, Maryland, pp 185–208Google Scholar
  54. Metz T (2016a) An African theory of social justice. In: Boisen C, Murray M (eds) Distributive justice debates in political and social thought: perspectives on finding a fair share. Routledge, Abington, pp 171–190Google Scholar
  55. Metz T (2016b) The nature of poverty as an unhuman condition. Res Publica 22(3):327–342CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Murphy L, Nagel T (2001) The myth of ownership: taxes and justice. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  57. Mutava C, Wanjala B (2017) Taxing for a more equal Kenya. Oxfam International, KenyaGoogle Scholar
  58. Oaks D (2008) Rights and responsibilities. In: Amitai E (ed) The essential communitarian reader. Rowman and Littlefield Publishers Inc., Lanham, Maryland, pp 97–106Google Scholar
  59. Odd-Helge F et al (2018) Building tax systems in fragile states: challenges, achievements and policy recommendations. Chr. Michelsen Institute and Norwegian Institute of International Affairs, NorwayGoogle Scholar
  60. Onazi O (2014) Before rights and responsibilities: an African ethos of citizenship. In: Onazi O (ed) African legal theory and contemporary problems: critical essays. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 153–172CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Onazi O (2017) Disability justice dictated by the surfeit of love: Simone Weil in Nigeria. Law Crit 28(1):1–22CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Owens T, Torrance T (2015) ‘I know my rights, but am I better off?’: institutions and disability in Uganda. J Dev Stud 52(1):22–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Oyaro (2013) Mozambique. Afr Disability Rights Yearb 1: 245–260Google Scholar
  64. Praeg L (2014) A report on Ubuntu. University of KwaZulu Natal Press, PietermaritzburgGoogle Scholar
  65. Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge MassachusettsGoogle Scholar
  66. Saffie F (2014) Taxes as practices of mutual recognition: towards a general theory of tax law. Thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of degree of Doctor of Philosophy. University of Edinburgh, EdinburghGoogle Scholar
  67. Seligman E (1925) Essays in taxation. Columbia University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  68. Seto P, Buha S (2006) Tax and disability: ability to pay and the taxation of difference. Univ Pennsylvania Law Rev 154:1053–1145CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Shughuru P (2013) Tanzania. Afr Disability Rights Yearb 1:341–357Google Scholar
  70. Silverman A et al (2015) Stumbling in their shoes: disability simulations reduced judged capabilities of disabled people. Soc Psychol Pers Sci 6(4):464–471CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Silvers A (1998) Formal justice. In: Silvers A et al (eds) Disability, difference, discrimination. Rowman and Littlefield Publishers Inc., Lanham, Maryland, pp 13–145Google Scholar
  72. Tangwa G (2000) The traditional African perception of a person: some implications for bioethics. Hast Cent Rep 30(5):39–43CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  73. Tutu D (1999) No future without forgiveness: a personal overview of South Africa’s truth and reconciliation commission. Random House, LondonCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Waghid Y (2015) On the (im)potentiality of an African philosophy of education to disrupt inhumanity. Educ Philos Theory 47(11):1240–1243CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. Wilkinson M (1994) Paying for public spending: is there a role for earmarked taxes? Fisc Stud 15(4):119–135CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  76. Wiredu K (1992) The moral foundations of an African culture. In: Wiredu K, Gyekye K (eds) Person and community: Ghanaian philosophical studies. The Council for Research in Values and Philosophy, Washington DC, pp 193–206Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of SouthamptonSouthamptonUK

Personalised recommendations