Advertisement

Self-Feeling pp 171-195 | Cite as

Appropriateness of Self-Feeling

  • Gerhard Kreuch
Chapter
Part of the Contributions to Phenomenology book series (CTPH, volume 107)

Abstract

This chapter explores if and to what extent self-feeling can go wrong. Notably, self-feeling cannot err in the awareness of mere existence. Whenever we have a self-feeling, this already entails our awareness that we exist. However, self-feelings can be called inappropriate based on the way they shape the overall experience of our individual lives. An appropriate self-feeling must display a middle way between being open to alternatives (criterion 1) and being stable over time (criterion 3). Also, appropriate self-feelings must enable openness to other people as people (criterion 2). In addition to these criteria coming from Ratcliffe’s theory of existential feelings, the philosophy of short-term, object-oriented emotions has additional criteria to offer for what they count as appropriate or inappropriate. First, the appropriateness of self-feelings can be evaluated with a look at its biological effects (criterion 4). Second, inappropriate self-feelings can harm our social fitness (criterion 5). Third, self-feelings need to display a certain amount of consistency with other mental states (criterion 6). Overall, six imperfect criteria are presented to evaluate the appropriateness of self-feelings. Importantly, there is no decisive, ultimate criterion to assess a particular self-feeling. All discussed criteria have their shortcomings. Nonetheless, in sum they can provide some guidance.

Literature

  1. Bilgrami, A. 2006. Self-knowledge and Resentment. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  2. Boyle, M. 2009. Two Kinds of Self-Knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXXVIII 1: 133–164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Damasio, A. 1994. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. New York: Putnam.Google Scholar
  4. De Sousa, R. 1987. The Rationality of Emotion. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Deonna, J., and F. Teroni. 2012. The Emotions: A Philosophical Introduction. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  6. Fasching, W. 2008. Consciousness, Self-consciousness, and Meditation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 7 (4): 463–483.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Frank, R.H. 1988. Passions Within Reason: The Strategic Role of Emotions. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
  8. Heidegger, M. 2006 [1927]. Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Niemeyer.Google Scholar
  9. Helm, B.W. 2001. Emotional Reason. Deliberation, Motivation, and the Nature of Value. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  10. ———. 2002. Felt Evaluations: A Theory of Pleasure and Pain. American Philosophical Quarterly 39 (1): 13–30.Google Scholar
  11. ———. 2011. Affektive Intentionalität: Holistisch und vielschichtig. In Affektive Intentionalität: Beiträge zur welterschließenden Funktion menschlicher Gefühle, ed. J. Slaby, A. Stephan, and H. Walter. Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
  12. Hofstede, G. 2001. Culture’s Consequences: Comparing Values, Behaviors, Institutions, and Organizations Across Nations. Thousand Oaks: Sage.Google Scholar
  13. Kant, I. 1974 [1790]. Kritik der Urteilskraft. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  14. Kenny, A. 1963. Action, Emotion, and Will. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  15. Kernberg, O. 1984. Severe Personality Disorders: Psychotherapeutic Strategies. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Kohut, H. 1971. The Analysis of the Self: A Systematic Approach to the Psychoanalytic Treatment of Narcissistic Personality Disorders. New York: International Universities Press.Google Scholar
  17. LeDoux, J. 1996. The Emotional Brain: The Mysterious Underpinnings of Emotional Life. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
  18. Lyons, W. 1980. Emotion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Markus, H.R., and S. Kitayama. 1991. Culture and the Self: Implications for Cognition, Emotion, and Motivation. Psychological Review 98 (2): 224–253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. ———. 2010. Cultures and Selves: A Cycle of Mutual Constitution. Perspectives on Psychological Science 5 (4): 420–430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. McDowell, J. 1998. Mind, Value, and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Metzinger, T. 2003. Being No One. The Self-model Theory of Subjectivity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  23. ———. 2009. The Ego-Tunnel. The Science of the Mind and the Myth of the Self. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  24. ———. 2011. The No-Self Alternative. In The Oxford Handbook of the Self, ed. S. Gallagher, 279–296. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Moran, R. 2001. Authority and Estrangement: An Essay on Self-knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Müller, J.M. 2011. Emotion, Wahrnehmung und evaluative Erkenntnis. In Affektive Intentionalität. Beiträge zur welterschließenden Funktion der menschlichen Gefühle, ed. J. Slaby, S. Achim, and H. Walter, 100–127. Paderborn: mentis.Google Scholar
  27. Ratcliffe, M. 2008. Feelings of Being. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  28. ———. 2015a. Experiences of Depression: A Study in Phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Reed, B. 2012. Fallibilism. Philosophy Compass 7 (9): 585–596.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Scheler, M. 1921. Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik: Neuer Versuch der Grundlegung eines ethischen Personalismus. Halle a. d. S.: Niemeyer.Google Scholar
  31. Schmidbauer, W. 1977. Die hilflosen Helfer. Reinbek bei Hamburg: Rowohlt.Google Scholar
  32. Siderits, M. 2011. Buddhist Non-Self: The No-Owner’s Manual. In The Oxford Handbook of the Self, ed. S. Gallagher, 297–315. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Slaby, J. 2008b. Gefühl und Weltbezug: Die menschliche Affektivität im Kontext einer neo-existentialistischen Konzeption von Personalität. Paderborn: mentis.Google Scholar
  34. Slaby, J., and A. Stephan. 2008. Affective Intentionality and Self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition 17 (2): 506–513.Google Scholar
  35. ———. 2011. Affektive Intentionalität, existenzielle Gefühle und Selbstbewusstsein. In Affektive Intentionalität. Beiträge zur welterschließenden Funktion der menschlichen Gefühle, ed. J. Slaby, A. Stephan, H. Walter, and S. Walter, 206–229. Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
  36. Stephan, A. 2012. Emotions, Existential Feelings, and Their Regulation. Emotion Review 4 (2): 157–162.Google Scholar
  37. Tappolet, C. 2000. Emotions et Valeurs. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.Google Scholar
  38. Taylor, C. 1985. Self-interpreting Animals. In Human Agency and Language, Philosophical Papers, ed. C. Taylor, vol. I, 45–76. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  39. Wiggins, D. 1987. A Sensible Subjectivism? In Needs, Values, Truth, ed. D. Wiggins, 185–214. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  40. Young, J.E., J.S. Klosko, and M.E. Weishaar. 2003. Schema Therapy: A Practitioner’s Guide. New York: Guilford Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  • Gerhard Kreuch
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of ViennaViennaAustria

Personalised recommendations