Advertisement

Jean Améry pp 105-118 | Cite as

Torture and Torturers

  • Eran Fish
Chapter

Abstract

In his account of torture, Jean Améry describes not only the act of torture and the experience of the person being tortured, but also the torturers themselves, with their particular psychology. Améry claims that the torture was done by people fully intent on inflicting pain, rather than by mere “bureaucrats of torture”, as some might argue. This description is important for two reasons. First, it is important for understanding the act of torture itself. Torture, I argue, is considered to be a unique moral wrong not for the suffering it inflicts, but for the cruelty it typically manifests. Secondly, the fact that the act of torture reflected something deep in the perpetrators’ personality may explain why blame for the crime remains appropriate long after it had been committed.

Keywords

Arendt Blameworthiness Cruelty Moral character Torture 

References

  1. Améry, J. (1980). Torture. In S. Rosenfeld & S. P. Rosenfeld (Trans.), At the Mind’s Limits (pp. 21–40). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Arendt, H. (1963). Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
  3. Augustine. (1994). Contra Faustum. In P. Schaff (Ed.), Vol. 4 of Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers (pp. 155–345). Peabody, MA: Hendrickson.Google Scholar
  4. Brandt, R. (1958). Blameworthiness and Obligation. In A. I. Melden (Ed.), Essays in Moral Philosophy (pp. 3–39). Seattle, WA: University of Washington Press.Google Scholar
  5. Elstein, D., & Hurka, T. (2009). From Thick to Thin: Two Moral Reduction Plans. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 39(4), 515–535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Hume, D. (1978). In L. A. Selby-Brigge (Ed.), A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  7. Hurka, T. (2006). Virtuous Act, Virtuous Dispositions. Analysis, 66(1), 69–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Kauppinen, A. (2015). Character and Blame in Hume and Beyond. In I. Fileva (Ed.), Perspectives on Character (pp. 46–62). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Kekes, J. (1996). Cruelty and Liberalism. Ethics, 106, 834–844.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Khoury, A. (2013). Synchronic and Diachronic Responsibility. Philosophical Studies, 165, 735–752.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Nelkin, D. K. (2015). Psychopaths, Incorrigible Racists, and the Faces of Responsibility. Ethics, 125, 357–390.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Putnam, H. (2002). The Entanglement of Fact and Value. In The Collapse of the Fact/Value Dichotomy and Other Essays (pp. 28–45). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Rorty, R. (1989). Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Sher, G. (2005). In Praise of Blame. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Shklar, J. (1984). Ordinary Vices. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Shue, H. (1978). Torture. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 7, 124–143.Google Scholar
  17. Sussman, D. (2005). What’s Wrong with Torture? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 33, 1–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Sverdlik, S. (1996). Motive and Rightness. Ethics, 106, 327–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Thomas, L. (1993). Vessels of Evil: American Slavery and the Holocaust. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  • Eran Fish
    • 1
  1. 1.Ludwig-Maximilian UniversityMunichGermany

Personalised recommendations