Advertisement

What Is a Destructive, Deforming Institution?

  • Michelle MaieseEmail author
  • Robert Hanna
Chapter

Abstract

Destructive, deforming social institutions are those that make it difficult or impossible for the people who belong to them to satisfy their true human needs. Drawing on Marcuse’s distinction between true human needs and false human needs, we argue that true human needs are universal across humanity and essentially bound up with human dignity in a Kantian sense. False human needs, in contrast, encompass anything that people desire, no matter how intensely or repeatedly, whose satisfaction represses, impedes, or outright destroys the satisfaction of true human needs. In contemporary neoliberal societies like the USA, people’s true human needs, both as individual and social beings, are systematically replaced by false human needs for money, property, and social status. Such collective sociopathy, we argue, can be understood as resulting from the systematic interplay of three factors: neoliberal ideology, a scientistic worldview, and coercive authoritarianism. What makes the social institutions within such societies destructive and deforming is that they centrally involve commodification, mechanization, coercion, the incentivization of desire, and false consciousness.

Keywords

Needs Dignity Collective sociopathy Neoliberal ideology Scientistic Authoritarianism 

References

  1. van Dijk, Ludger, and Erik Rietveld. 2017. Foregrounding sociomaterial practice in our understanding of affordances: The skilled intentionality framework. Frontiers in Psychology 7: 1969.Google Scholar
  2. Fromm, Erich. 1941. The fear of freedom. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  3. Hamann, Trent. 2009. Neoliberalism, governmentality, and ethics. Foucault Studies 6: 37–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Hanna, Robert. 2018b. The rational human condition. Vol. 2—Deep freedom and real persons: A study in metaphysics. New York: Nova Science.Google Scholar
  5. ———. 2018c. The rational human condition. Vol. 3—Kantian ethics and human existence: A study in moral philosophy. New York: Nova Science.Google Scholar
  6. Harvey, David. 2005. A brief history of neoliberalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Lofgren, Mike. 2014. Anatomy of the deep state. Moyers and Company, February 21. http://billmoyers.com/2014/02/21/anatomy-of-the-deep-state/.
  8. Marcuse, Herbert. 1964. One dimensional man. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
  9. Mihai, Michaela. 2016. Theorizing change: Between reflective judgment and the inertia of political habitus. European Journal of Political Theory 15 (1): 22–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Mühlhoff, Rainer, and Jan Slaby. 2017. Immersion at work: Affect and power in post-Fordist work Cultures. In Affect in relation: Families, places, technologies, ed. B. Röttger-Rössler and J. Slaby, 1–21. New York: Routledge. https://www.academia.edu/32615026/Immersion_at_work_Affect_and_power_in_post-Fordist_work_cultures.Google Scholar
  11. Reporters Without Borders. 2018. https://rsf.org/en.
  12. Scott, James C. 1998. Seeing like a state. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Slaby, Jan. 2016. Relational affect. https://www.academia.edu/25728787/Relational_Affect.
  14. Thoreau, Henry David. 1995. Walden. In H.D. Thoreau, Walden and on the duty of civil disobedience. https://www.gutenberg.org/files/205/205-h/205-h.htm.
  15. Watermeyer, Richard, and Mark Olssen. 2016. “Excellence” and exclusion: The individual costs of institutional competitiveness. Minerva 54: 201–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Wikipedia. 2018a. Military-industrial complex. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Military%E2%80%93industrial_complex.
  17. ———. 2018b. The power elite. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_Power_Elite.

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Emmanuel CollegeBostonUSA
  2. 2.Independent PhilosopherBoulderUSA

Personalised recommendations