Advertisement

The Cognitive Effects on Early and Late Vision and Their Epistemological Impact

  • Athanassios RaftopoulosEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Palgrave Innovations in Philosophy book series (PIIP)

Abstract

In this chapter, I examine the repercussions of the cognitive impenetrability of early vision and cognitive penetrability of late vision for the epistemic role of visual perception and for the constructivist claim that our access to the world is mediated through our concepts.

References

  1. Attneave, F. (1971). Multistability in perception. Scientific American, 225, 63–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Britz, J., & Pitts, M. (2011). Perceptual reversals during binocular rivalry: ERP components and their concomitant source differences. Psychophysiology, 48, 1489–1498.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Driver, J., & Baylis, G. S. (1996). Eye-assignment and figure-ground segregation in short-term visual matching. Cognitive Psychology, 31, 248–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Hochberg, J., & Peterson, M. A. (1987). Piecemeal organization and cognitive components in object perception. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 116, 370–380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Kornmeier, J., & Bach, M. (2009). Object perception: When our brain is impressed but we do not notice it. Journal of Vision, 9(1), 1–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Lyons, J. (2011). Circularity, reliability, and the cognitive penetrability of perception. Philosophical Issues, 21, The Epistemology of Perception, 289–311.Google Scholar
  7. Peterson, M. A., & Gibson, B. S. (1994). Must figure-ground organization precede object recognition? An assumption in peril. Psychological Science, 5, 253–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Peterson, M. A., & Hochberg, J. (1983). Opposed set-measurements procedure: A quantitative analysis of the role of local cues and intention in form perception. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 9, 183–193.Google Scholar
  9. Pitts, M., Nerger, J., & Davis, T. J. R. (2007). Electrophysiological correlates of perceptual reversals for three different types of multistable images. Journal of Vision, 7(1), 1–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Raftopoulos, A. (2006). Defending realism on the proper ground. Philosophical Psychology, 19(1), 1–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Raftopoulos, A. (2009). Cognition and Perception: How Do Psychology and Neural Science Inform Philosophy? Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Raftopoulos, A. (2011). Ambiguous figures and representationalism. Synthese, 181, 489–514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Raftopoulos, A. (2014). The cognitive impenetrability of the content of early vision is a necessary and sufficient condition for purely nonconceptual content. Philosophical Psychology, 27(5), 601–620.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Raftopoulos, A. (2015). The cognitive impenetrability of perception and theory-ladenness. Journal of General Philosophy of Science, 46(1), 87–103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Siegel, S. (2011). Cognitive penetrability and perceptual justification. Nous, 46, 201–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Siegel, S. (2013a). The epistemic impact of the etiology of experience. Philosophical Studies, 162, 697–722.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Siegel, S. (2013b). Can selection effects influence the rational role of experience? In T. Gelder (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology (Vol. 4, pp. 240–270). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Siegel, S. (2016). How is wishful seeing like wishful thinking? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.  https://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PsychologyUniversity of CyprusNicosiaCyprus

Personalised recommendations