Advertisement

Ascetic Practices, Hermeneutical Cycles and Ecosophical Endurance

  • Ron Welters
Chapter
Part of the Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy book series (LOET, volume 37)

Abstract

After discussing the environmental effects of sport practices and putting a metabletic view on sport to the test, I now will turn to philosophy of sport as an academic discipline. Like other branches of applied philosophy, such as animal ethics and environmental philosophy, it started off in the early seventies of the previous century. Currently, it seems locked in a binary view. On the one hand narrow internalists, or formalists, argue that sports are uniquely constituted by their rules. This point of view can be referred to as the autotelic stance. Herein sport is considered an end in itself, constitued by rules and (eventually) shared conventions on how to play or race well. Broad internalists, or interpretivists, on the other hand, contend that sport is more than just a gratuitous and playful end in itself. In this line of reasoning sport also can be a means toward other ends: national pride, prize money, a ruthless quest for records, challenging the existing order or advancing international peace. This is the heterotelic view.

In this chapter I will revitalise the reflection on sport as a dimension of the human condition by attempting to move beyond the binary opposition of internalism and externalism. I will do so by focussing on the potentially positive aspects of the concept of agon, a term which denotes struggle or contest. As an ‘agonal’ or competitive social practice, sport turns out to be a means to an end, in the sense that it surpasses the concept of sport as self-referential play: seeking knowledge, understanding the human condition, and cultivating virtue. I argue that this agonistic heterotelic view seems the better option.

In order to strengthen my claims I will uptake, broaden and deepen Peter Sloterdijk’s ascetology already introduced in previous chapters. The bottom line of his call for a change for the better is that we have to become aware of the fact that our ‘ascetic planet’ is inhabited by individuals who are constantly and relentlessly training themselves. This may be self-focused, but it may also have a broader scope: we train ourselves to become better humans, contributing to a just and sustainable society. Paradoxically, however, this will only work when we become aware of our exercises as forms of life that engage the whole practicing person.

A broad internal hermeneutic interpretation and furthering of endurance sport, especially cycling, can enrich our understanding of this sports activity as a form of asceticism. By following and furthering this ascetological imperative we can elaborate a view on cycling as an upwardly oriented ‘spiral’ that can contribute not only to self-knowledge and self-improvement on the individual level (metanoia), but also to an ‘ecosophical renaissance’ on the collective level.

Keywords

Autotelic view Heterotelic view Ascetology Hermeneutic cycles 

References

  1. Caddick, N., and E. Ryall. 2012. The social construction of ‘mental toughness’ – A fascistoid ideology? Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 39 (1): 137–154.  https://doi.org/10.1080/00948705.2012.675068.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Edgar, A. 2013. A hermeneutics of sport. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 7 (1): 140–167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Fry, J. 2014. Sport. In The Bloomsbury companion to the philosophy of sport, ed. C. Torres, 371–373. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
  4. Fusche Moe, V. 2014. The philosophy of sport and continental philosophy. In The Bloomsbury companion to the philosophy of sport, ed. C. Torres, 52–65. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
  5. Giesen, P. 2011. Peter Sloterdijk, Duitse filosoof: Naar de sportschool om de planeet te redden. De Volkskrant, April 30 2011: 7–8.Google Scholar
  6. Grondin, J. 2015. What is the hermeneutical circle? (First draft of an essay to be published) In: The Blackwell companion to hermeneutics, Keane N. and C. Lawn eds., (2016). Available at https://www.academia.edu/13944229/What_is_the_hermeneutical_circle?auto=download&campaign=weekly_digest. Accessed 3Sept 2015.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Heidegger, M. 1927/2008. Being and time. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
  8. Huizinga, J. 1955. Homo ludens – A study of the play-element in culture. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
  9. James, W. 1907. The energies of man. The American magazine (reprint). Available at: https://archive.org/stream/energiesofmen00jameuoft/energiesofmen00jameuoft_djvu.txt
  10. Kirsch, A. 2015. Against cynicism – A philosopher’s brilliant reasons for living. Available at: http://www.newrepublic.com/article/113387/peter-sloterdijks-philosophy-gives-reasons-living
  11. Krajeweski, B. 1989. Critique of cynical reason, Peter Sloterdijk. Journal of the Midwest Modern Language Association 22 (1): 61–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Loland, S. 1995. Coubertin’s ideology of Olympism from the perspective of the history of ideas. Olympika: Nternational Journal of Olympic Studies (4): 49–77.Google Scholar
  13. ———. 2003. Technology in sport: Three ideal-typical views and their implications. Available at: http://idrottsforum.org/articles/loland/loland_2.html
  14. Lopez Frias, J. 2014. Internalism. In Bloomsbury companion to the philosophy of sport, ed. C. Torres, 362–364. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
  15. Lopez Frias, J., and X. Montfort. 2015. A hermeneutical analysis of the internalist approach in the philosophy of sport. Physical Culture and Sport LXVII: 5–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Lunt, D., and M. Dyreson. 2014. A history of philosophic ideas about sport. In The Bloomsbury companion to the philosophy of sport, ed. C. Torres, 17–37. New York: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
  17. McNamee, M. 2015. The spirit of sport and the World Anti-Doping Code. Abingdon. Routledge.Google Scholar
  18. Meier, K. 1988. Triad trickery: Playing with sport and games. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 15: 11–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Nepper Larsen, S. 2010. Becoming a cyclist – Phenomenological reflections on cycling. In Cycling philosophy for everyone: A philosophical tour de force, ed. J. Ilundáin-Agurruza and M. Austin, 27–39. Chichester: Wiley Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Nietzsche, F.W. 2005. Thus spoke Zarathustra: A book for everyone and nobody. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Piacente, A. 2015. Reverse play: Towards a philosophy from sport. Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 9 (1): 58–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Reid, H.L. 2009. Sport, philosophy, and the quest for knowledge. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 36 (1): 40–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Sloterdijk, P. 1983/1987. Critique of cynical reason. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  24. ———. 2009/2013. You must change your life – On anthropotechnics. Cambridge/Malden: Polity Press.Google Scholar
  25. Steenbergen, J. 2004. Grenzen aan de sport. Een theoretische analyse van het sportbegrip. Maarssen: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  26. Suits, B. 1978/2005. The grasshopper: Games, life, and utopia. Ontario: Broadview Press.Google Scholar
  27. ———. 1988. Tricky triad: Games, play, and sport. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 15: 1–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Tuncel, Y. 2013. Agon in Nietzsche. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Wittgenstein, L. 1953/1978. Philosophical investigations. London: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  30. Zwart, H. 2010. Wordt ons leven anders? Over genomics en zelfarbeid – Beschouwingen naar aanleiding van Peter Sloterdijks Du musst dein Leben ändern. Tijdschrift voor Gezondheidszorg en Ethiek 2 (20): 73–76.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  • Ron Welters
    • 1
  1. 1.Institute for Science in Society, Faculty of ScienceRadboud UniversityNijmegenThe Netherlands

Personalised recommendations