Advertisement

Answering Three Ecosophical Questions: Asceticism

  • Ron Welters
Chapter
Part of the Library of Ethics and Applied Philosophy book series (LOET, volume 37)

Abstract

Sigmund Loland ends his Outline of an Ecosophy of Sport (1996), advanced in the previous chapter, by proposing three pivotal questions that have to be taken into account when it comes to the sport-ecosophical litmus-test.
  1. 1.

    What are the implications of the norm on ecosophical joy in my specific sport practice?

     
  2. 2.

    How should I, in my sport context, relate to norms for developing skills in width and depth, for playing to win and for applying only ecosophically sound sport technology?

     
  3. 3.

    What can be done to promote sport training and competition in closeness to nature?

     
As a practical philosopher and as a philosophical practitioner, I now will try to give provisional answers to these pivotal questions. I will do so from the perspective of (outdoor) endurance sports. To focus my thoughts, I will concentrate on running and particularly cycling, paved and unpaved, from elite athletes to dedicated age-groupers and joggers and weekend warriors.

Endurance sports do not fare well in celebrating the multitude of motor and physical skills that Loland seems to presuppose. They are about diligence, repetition and sticking to a program in order to be able to cover a certain distance or to complete a race. Fostering endurance is a continuum of work in diverse physical states, rather than practicing for a few moments of exhilarating joy. Also Loland acknowledges the benefits of a dedicated training regimen. Longer periods of hard and monotonous work can to some extent be ecosophically justified, Loland reasons, but just as an instrumental means to an end: “Work is acceptable as a means to increased joy and perfection” (p. 80).

Although they may seem fairly dull and repetitive indeed, sports that take a substantial effort are increasingly popular with the sedentary, urban and over-stimulated masses in the search for counterbalance, though. A certain physical constitution obviously is advantageous when it comes to endurance sports. Next to possessing basic health, a somewhat slim body may be helpful as a point of departure for fresh(wo)men in running and cycling. However, perseverance and stamina are far more important when it comes to cultivating staying power—and these ascetic virtues are within reach for most of us. Therefore endurance sports can more easily effect a change for the better than skill and agility demanding elite sports.

Because of this high potential for change, I now (in the tough spirit of endurance sport) will try to answer the three key questions Loland proposes as a guideline for ecosophically good sport. To strengthen my critical assessment of Loland’s sport-ecosophical blueprint, Peter Sloterdijk’s plea for a radical change of our lifestyle by means of a well-understood ‘ascetology’ will be put in position. If properly performed, this general training theory will result in metanoia, a radical personal change of an unsustainable life-style, or at the collective level even in a ‘renaissance’ of durable virtues.

Keywords

Ecosophical questions Endurance sports Ascetology Durable virtues 

References

  1. Arnoldussen, P. 2008. Amsterdam 1928: de Spelen in Nederland. Amsterdam: Thomas Rap.Google Scholar
  2. Gorris, L., and D. Kurbjuweit. 2008. Philosopher Peter Sloterdijk on the Tour de France: ‘The riders are just regular employees.’ Der Spiegel Online International. http://www.spiegel.de/international/europe/philosopher-peter-sloterdijk-on-the-tour-de-france-the-riders-are-just-regular-employees-a-565111.html. Accessed 9 September 2017.
  3. Greening, J.C. 2011. A fresh perspective: Parkour and the infinite potentiality of the environment. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the International Association for the Philosophy of Sport. 8–11 September, New York, Rochester.Google Scholar
  4. Harris, T. 2009. Sport: Almost everything you ever wanted to know. London: Penguin Random House.Google Scholar
  5. Hochstetler, D., and P. Hopsicker. 2012. The heights of humanity: Endurance sport and the strenuous mood. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 39 (1): 117–136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Hohrod, G., and M. Eschbach. 1912. Ode to sport. V Olympiad. Stockholm. http://library.la84.org/OlympicInformationCenter/OlympicReview/2000/OREXXVI32/OREXXVI32x.pdf. Accesses 12 November 2017.
  7. Howe, L. 2008. Remote sport: Risk and self-knowledge in wilder spaces. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 35: 1–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. James, W. 1977. The writings of William James (ed. McDermott, J.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  9. Kilpatrick, D. 2010. Poetics and the beautiful game. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the International Association for the Philosophy of Sport, 15–19 September, Italy, Rome.Google Scholar
  10. Krabbé, T. 1978/2016. The rider. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
  11. Kreft, L. 2010. Lost in translation: Heidegger and ski jumping in Slovenia. Physical Culture & Sport Studies & Research 49: 13–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Kretchmar, S.R., and J. Hwang. 2010. Aristotle’s golden mean: Its implications for the doping debate. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 37 (1): 102–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Lemmens, P. 2008. Gedreven door techniek. De menselijke conditie en de biotechnologische revolutie (Driven by technology. The human condition and the biotechnology revolution). Oisterwijk: Box Press.Google Scholar
  14. Loland, S. 1996. Outline of an ecosophy of sport. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 23: 70–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. ———. 2002. Technology in sport: Three ideal-typical views and their implications. http://idrottsforum.org/articles/loland/loland_2.html. Accessed 9 September 2017.
  16. McDonald, K. 2013. Long course for life – Ken Glah’s 10 tips for Ironman longevity. Triathlete Europe (February), pp. 62–68.Google Scholar
  17. Nepper Larsen, S. 2010. Becoming a cyclist. Phenomenological reflections on cycling. In Cycling philosophy for everyone: A philosophical tour de force, ed. J. Ilundáin-Agurruza and M. Austin, 27–39. Chichester: Wiley Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Pirsig, R.M. 1974. Zen and the art of motorcycle maintenance: An inquiry into values. New York: William Morrow.Google Scholar
  19. Reid, H.L. 2002. The philosophical athlete. Durham: Carolina Academic Press.Google Scholar
  20. ———. 2009. Sport, philosophy, and the quest for knowledge. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 36 (1): 40–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Sloterdijk, P. 2009/2013. You must change your life. On anthropotechnics. Cambridge: Malden.Google Scholar
  22. Spinney, J. 2006. A place of sense: A kinaesthetic ethnography of cyclists on Mont Ventoux. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 24: 709–732.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Van den Berg, J.H. 1973. De reflex: Metabletische tegelijk maatschappijkritische studie. Nijkerk: Calllenbach.Google Scholar
  24. Van den Bossche, M. 2005. De passie van Marc Van den Bossche: Wielrennen. Rotterdam: Lemniscaat.Google Scholar
  25. Verkuil, D. 2015. We lopen steeds massaler, maar ook steeds langzamer. Nederlandse Omroep Stichting. https://nos.nl/artikel/2029707-we-lopen-steeds-massaler-maar-ook-steeds-langzamer.html. Accessed 2 November 2017.
  26. Welters, R. 2011. Van Eyserbosweg naar Eyserbosweg: Fietsfilosofische plaatservaringen. In Filosofische beschouwingen over plaats: Verbondenheid met natuur en landschap, ed. R. van den Born, M. Drenthen, P. Lemmens, and T. van Slobbe, 51–70. Zeist: KNNV.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  • Ron Welters
    • 1
  1. 1.Institute for Science in Society, Faculty of ScienceRadboud UniversityNijmegenThe Netherlands

Personalised recommendations