Advertisement

Entity–Activity Dualism

  • Beate Krickel
Chapter
Part of the Studies in Brain and Mind book series (SIBM, volume 13)

Abstract

What kinds of things are we committed to if AE-mechanisms exist? Defenders of the AE-approach to mechanisms argue that mechanisms are organized entities and activities. This entity–activity dualism is understood as a metaphysical claim: the fundamental units of mechanisms are entities and activities that cannot be reduced to anything more fundamental. In this chapter I investigate this claim. In the first section, I analyze the notion of an entity. In the second section, I illuminate the notion of an activity. To combine the results from these two sections, and in order to accommodate the criticisms of entity–activity dualism that I bring forward, in the third section I introduce the notion of an entity-involving occurrent. In the fourth section, I elaborate on one central motivation for introducing the notion of an activity: activities are supposed to be essentially causal, and thus are the kinds of things that bring causation into the world. How this is supposed to happen is, so far, not well understood. I illuminate this idea and introduce a new account of causation: activity causation.

References

  1. Anscombe, G. E. M. (1971). Causality and determinism. London: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Austin, C. J. (2016). The ontology of organisms: Mechanistic modules or patterned processes? Biology and Philosophy, 31, 639–662.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9533-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Beebee, H. (2004). Causing and nothingness. In L. A. Paul, E. J. Hall, & J. Collins (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 291–308). Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  4. Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  5. Broad, C. D. (1952). Ethics and the history of philosophy: Selected essays. Westport: Hyperion Press.Google Scholar
  6. Campaner, R. (2006). Mechanisms and counterfactuals: A different glimpse of the (secret?) connexion. Philosophica, 77, 15–44.Google Scholar
  7. Cartwright, N. (1994). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.  https://doi.org/10.1093/0198235070.001.0001.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Casini, L. (2016). Can interventions rescue glennan mechanistic account of causality? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 67, 1155–1183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Darden, L. (2008). Thinking again about biological mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 75, 958–969.  https://doi.org/10.1086/594538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. DiFrisco, J. (2016). Time scales and levels of organization. Erkenntnis, 1–24.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-016-9844-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Dowe, P. (2004). Causes are physically connected to their effects: Why preventers and omissions are not causes. In C. Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of science (pp. 189–196). Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  13. Felline, L. (2016). Mechanistic causality and the bottoming-out problem. In L. Felline, A. Ledda, & F. Paoli (Eds.), New developments in logic and philosophy of science (pp. 257–266). London: College Publications.Google Scholar
  14. Fischer, F. (2016). Philosophy of time : A slightly opinionated introduction. Kriterion – Journal of Philosophy, 30, 3–28.Google Scholar
  15. Glennan, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 49–71.  https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00172853.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Glennan, S. (2010). Mechanisms, causes, and the layered model of the world. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 362–381.  https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2010.00375.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Glennan, S. (2011). Singular and general causal relations: A mechanist perspective. Causality in the Sciences, 789–817.  https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199574131.003.0037.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Glennan, S. (2017). The new mechanical philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Harré, R., & Madden, E. H. (1975). Causal powers: A theory of natural necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  20. Hitchcock, C., & Knobe, J. (2009). Cause and norm. Journal of Philosophy, 106, 587–612.  https://doi.org/10.5840/jphil20091061128.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Illari, P. M. K., & Williamson, J. (2011). Mechanisms are real and local. In Causality in the sciences (pp. 818–844). Oxford: Oxford University Press.  https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199574131.003.0038.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Illari, P. M. K., & Williamson, J. (2013). In defence of activities. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 44, 69–83.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-013-9217-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Kaiser, M. I. (2015). Reductive explanation in the biological sciences (History, philosophy and theory of the life sciences). Cham: Springer International Publishing.Google Scholar
  24. Keil, G. (2000). Handeln Und Verursachen. Klostermann.Google Scholar
  25. Kuhlmann, M., & Glennan, S. (2014). On the relation between quantum mechanical and neo-mechanistic ontologies and explanatory strategies. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 4, 337–359.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-014-0088-3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Lewis, D. (2001). On the plurality of worlds. Humanities. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  27. Machamer, P. (2004). Activities and causation: The metaphysics and epistemology of mechanisms. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 18, 27–39.  https://doi.org/10.1080/02698590412331289242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. McGrath, S. (2005). Causation by omission: A Dilemma. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 123, 125–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. L. (2011). Getting causes from powers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Persson, J. (2010). Activity-based accounts of mechanism and the threat of polygenic effects. Erkenntnis, 72, 135–149.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-009-9195-5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Psillos, S. (2004). A glimpse of the secret connexion: Harmonizing mechanisms with counterfactuals. Perspectives on Science, 12, 288–319.  https://doi.org/10.1162/1063614042795426.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Rescher, N. (2000). Process philosophy: A survey of basic issues. Philadelphia: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Rodríguez Pereyra, G. (2002). Resemblance nominalism: A solution to the problem of universals. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2016). Nominalism in metaphysics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Winter 201. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.Google Scholar
  36. Russell, B. (1912). On the notion of cause. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 13, 1–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Schaffer, J. (2000). Causation by disconnection. Philosophy of Science, 67, 285–300.  https://doi.org/10.1086/392776.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Schaffer, J. (2003). Is there a fundamental level. Noûs, 37, 498–517.  https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0068.00448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Schark, M. (2012). Lebewesen versus Dinge, Eine metaphysische Studie. Berlin/Boston: De Gruyter.  https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110926194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Seibt, J. (2016). Process philosophy. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Winter 201. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.Google Scholar
  41. Strevens, M. (2013). Causality reunified. Erkenntnis, 78, 299–320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Tabery, J. G. (2004). Synthesizing activities and interactions in the concept of a mechanism*. Philosophy of Science, 71, 1–15.  https://doi.org/10.1086/381409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Torres, P. J. (2009). A modified conception of mechanisms. Erkenntnis, 71, 233–251. https://doi.org/10.1007/sl.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Weber, M. (2005). Philosophy of experimental biology (Cambridge studies in philosophy and biology). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Weiskopf, D. A. (2011). Models and mechanisms in psychological explanation. Synthese, 183, 313–338.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-011-9958-9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Whitehead, A. N. (1929). Process and reality: An essay in cosmology. Gifford Lectures delivered in the University of Edinburgh during the session 1927–1928. New York: Cambrdige University Press.Google Scholar
  47. Willemsen, P. (2016). Omissions and expectations: A new approach to the things we failed to do. Synthese, 195, 1587–1614.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  • Beate Krickel
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of Philosophy IIRuhr-University BochumBochumGermany

Personalised recommendations