Advertisement

The Waning of Essentialism

  • Joseph Agassi
Chapter
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 401)

Abstract

John O. Wisdom (1947) says, [new-style] analytic philosophy has resulted from a radical change in our theory of definition, and the resulting devaluation of the place of essential definitions in science and philosophy. Most traditional and most current metaphysics are deeply involved with essential definitions. This invites the support of the proposal of Stuart Hampshire to salvage as much of metaphysics as possible. It is the proposal to correct Wittgenstein’s erroneous demand to oust all metaphysics by limiting it to the demand to oust metaphysical systems that rest on essential definitions, and to rectify logic accordingly. This is tantamount to the suggestion to oust the pretense to know what scientific theories will win assent and keep it to the end of days. It is possible to restrict further: whenever possible, we should reinterpret essential definitions to read them as conjectures. Perhaps surprisingly this proposal tallies with comments made by even the most ardent and significant members of the analytic school, such as Neurath and Carnap, not to mention Hintikka: insofar as metaphysics was ancillary to science, they all agreed, they did not object to it. This concession fully reverses their radicalism. It was a great loss that they ignored Wisdom. The limitation of anti-metaphysics to anti-essentialism is a modification that tallies with the current pervasive dissent from Wittgenstein in the analytic school, namely, the rejection of any grammatical criterion of demarcation of metaphysics Wittgenstein-style. This allows for the possible recognition of the value of some metaphysics.

References

  1. Agassi, J. (1995b). Naming and necessity: A second look. Iyyun, 44, 243–272.Google Scholar
  2. Bar-Am, N. (2008). Extensionalism: The revolution in logic. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bar-Am, N., & Agassi, J. (2014). Meaning: from parmenides to Wittgenstein: Philosophy as ‘footnotes to parmenides. Conceptus, 41, 188–208.Google Scholar
  4. Ben-Yami, H. (2017). Vagueness and family resemblance. In Glock, 2017, pp. 407–419.Google Scholar
  5. Boole, G. (1847). The Mathematical Analysis of Logic.Google Scholar
  6. Carter, W. R. (1989). The elements of metaphysics. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Duhem, P. (1905). Physics of a believer. In The aim and structure of physical theories. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard. University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Lejewski, C. (1954). Logic and existence. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 5, 104–119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Lenin, V. I. (1909). Materialism and empirio-criticism. Google Scholar
  11. Linsky, L. (1967). Referring. New York: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
  12. McCutcheon, F. (2001). Religion within the limits of language alone: Wittgenstein on philosophy and religion. Florence: Taylor and Francis.Google Scholar
  13. Munz, P. (2004). Beyond Wittgenstein’s Poker: New light on Popper and Wittgenstein. Hampshire/Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  14. Pelletier, F. J., & Linsky B. (2009). Russell vs. Frege on definite descriptions as singular terms. In Griffin & Jacquette, 2009, pp. 40–64.Google Scholar
  15. Pepper, S. C. (1942). World hypotheses: A study in evidence. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  16. Pichler, A., & Säätelä, S. (Eds.). (2005). Wittgenstein: The philosopher and his works. Bergen: The Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen.Google Scholar
  17. Popper, K. ([1935] 1959). The logic of scientific discovery. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
  18. Quine, W. Van O. (1947). On universals. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 12, 74–84.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Quine, W. Van O. (1988). A comment on Agassi’s remarks. Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie, 19, 117–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Quine, W. Van O. (1990). Pursuit of truth. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Quine, W. Van O. (2008). Confessions of a confirmed extensionalist: And other essays. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Russell, B. (1914). Our knowledge of the external world: As a field for scientific method in philosophy. London: G. Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
  24. Sass, L. (2001). Deep disquietudes: Reflections on Wittgenstein as antiphilosopher. In Wittgenstein: Biography and philosophy (pp. 98–155). Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Sigwart, C. (1895). Logic: The judgement, concept and inference.Google Scholar
  26. Watkins, J. (1957b). Farewell to the paradigm case argument. Analysis, 18, 25–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Wittgenstein, L. (1938). Lectures on religious belief. http://www.depa.univ-paris8.fr/IMG/pdf/Lectures_on_Religious_Belief.pdf
  28. Wittgenstein, L. ([1969] 1975). On certainty (D. Paul, & G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.).Google Scholar
  29. Wittgenstein, L. (1975). Lectures on the foundations of mathematics, Cambridge, 1939. Edited by Cora diamond from the notes of R. G. Bosanquet, Norman Malcolm, Rush Rhees, & Yorick Smythies.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  • Joseph Agassi
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyTel Aviv UniversityTel AvivIsrael

Personalised recommendations