Advertisement

Effective Validity: A Generalized Logic for Stable Approximate Inference

  • Robert H. C. MoirEmail author
Conference paper
Part of the Fields Institute Communications book series (FIC, volume 82)

Abstract

The traditional approach in philosophy of using logic to reconstruct scientific theories and methods operates by presenting or representing a scientific theory or method in a specialized formal language. The logic of such languages is deductive, which makes this approach effective for those aspects of science that use deductive methods or for which deductive inference provides a good idealization. Many theories and methods in science, however, use non-deductive forms of approximation. Approximate inferences, which produce approximately correct conclusions and do so only under restricted conditions before becoming unreliable, behave in a fundamentally different way. In the interest of developing accurate models of the structure of inference methods in scientific practice, the focus of this paper, we need conceptual tools that can faithfully represent the structure and behaviour of inference in scientific practice. To this end I propose a generalization of the traditional notion of logical validity, called effective validity, that captures the form of approximate inferences typically used in applied mathematics and computational science. I provide simple examples of approximate inference in mathematical modeling to show how a logic based on effectively valid inference can directly, faithfully represent a wide variety of the forms of inference used in scientific practice. I conclude by discussing how such a generalized logic of scientific inference can provide a richer understanding of problem-solving and mathematical modeling processes.

Notes

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank David Stoutemyer, Chris Smeenk, Erik Curiel and an anonymous reviewer for their valuable comments.

References

  1. 1.
    Batterman RW (2002) The devil in the details: asymptotic reasoning in explanation, reduction, and emergence. Oxford University Press, OxfordzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  2. 2.
    Corless RM (1994) Error backward. In: Kloeden PE, Palmer KT (eds) Chaotic numerics: an international workshop on the approximation and computation of complicated dynamical behavior, Deakin University, Geelong, Australia, July 12–16, 1993, vol 172. American Mathematical Society, ProvidenceGoogle Scholar
  3. 3.
    Corless RM, Fillion N (2013) A graduate introduction to numerical methods. Springer, BerlinCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. 4.
    Fillion N, Corless RM (2014) On the epistemological analysis of modeling and computational error in the mathematical sciences. Synthese 191(7):1451–1467MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 5.
    Fillion N, Moir RHC (2018) Explanation and abstraction from a backward-error analytic perspective. Eur J Philos Sci 8(3):735–759. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-018-0208-6 MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. 6.
    Goldstein H, Poole CP, Safko JL (2002) Classical mechanics. Addison-Wesley, BostonzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Hairer E, Lubich C, Wanner G (2006) Geometric numerical integration: structure-preserving algorithms for ordinary differential equations. Springer, BerlinzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  8. 8.
    Harper WL (2011) Isaac Newton’s scientific method. Oxford University Press, New YorkzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Hempel C (1965) Aspects of scientific explanation, and other essays in the philosophy of science. Free Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  10. 10.
    Lawden DF (1989) Elliptic functions and applications. Springer, BerlinCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. 11.
    Moir RHC (2010) Reconsidering backward error analysis for ordinary differential equations. MSc Thesis, The University of Western OntarioGoogle Scholar
  12. 12.
    Moir RHC (2013) Structures in real theory application: a study in feasible epistemology. PhD Thesis, The University of Western OntarioGoogle Scholar
  13. 13.
    Moir RHC (2018) Feasible computation: methodological contributions of computational science. In: Cuffaro ME, Fletcher SC (eds) Physical perspectives on computation, computational perspectives on physics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 172–194CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. 14.
    Oppenheim P, Putnam H (1958) Unity of science as a working hypothesis. Minn Stud Philos Sci 2:3–36Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    Suppe F (1974) The structure of scientific theories. University of Illinois Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  16. 16.
    Suppes P (1969) Models of data. Springer, BerlinCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. 17.
    Suppes P (2002) Representation and invariance of scientific structures. CSLI Publications, StanfordzbMATHGoogle Scholar
  18. 18.
    van Fraassen BC (1970) On the extension of Beth’s semantics of physical theories. Philos Sci 37(3):325–339MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 19.
    van Fraassen BC (1980) The scientific image. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. 20.
    van Fraassen BC (2006) Representation: the problem for structuralism. Philos Sci 73(5):536–547CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. 21.
    Voevodsky V et al (2013) Homotopy type theory: Univalent foundations of mathematics. Institute for Advanced Study (Princeton), The Univalent Foundations Program, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  22. 22.
    Wallace D (2006) In defence of naiveté: the conceptual status of Lagrangian quantum field theory. Synthese 151(1):33–80MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. 23.
    Wilson M (2006) Wandering significance: an essay on conceptual behavior. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. 24.
    Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: piecewise approximations to reality. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media, LLC, part of Springer Nature 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Computer ScienceThe University of Western OntarioLondonCanada

Personalised recommendations