Advertisement

Can the Person Affecting Restriction Solve the Problems in Population Ethics?

Chapter
Part of the International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine book series (LIME, volume 35)

Abstract

The person-affecting restriction, in its slogan form, states that an outcome can be better than another only if it is better for someone. It has a strong intuitive appeal and several theorists have suggested that it avoids certain counterintuitive implications in population ethics. At the same time, the restriction has highly counterintuitive implications and yields non-transitive orderings in some nonidentity cases. Many theorists have taken this criticism to be decisive. Recently, however, there have been some reformulations of the restriction, suggesting that the restriction survives this “old” criticism. This paper investigates the viability of those reformulations, which are versions of “Comparativism,” and argues that most of them either have counterintuitive implications or are extensionally equivalent with impersonal theories, but that “Soft Comparativism” seems to have an advantage over impersonal theories.

Keywords

Person-affecting restriction Population ethics The repugnant conclusion Broome Parfit Temkin Comparativism Non-transitive orderings 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Arrhenius, G. 2000a. Future generations: A challenge for moral theory. Uppsala: University Printers (F.D. Diss.).Google Scholar
  2. Arrhenius, G. 2000b. An impossibility theorem for welfarist axiologies. Economics & Philosophy 16: 247–266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Arrhenius, G. 2003a. Feldman’s desert-adjusted utilitarianism and population ethics. Utilitas 15(2): 225–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Arrhenius, G. 2003b. The person affecting restriction, comparativism, and the moral status of potential people. Ethical Perspectives 10 (3–4): 185–195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Arrhenius, G. 2005. The paradoxes of future generations and normative theory. In The repugnant conclusion, eds. J. Ryberg and T. Tännsjö, 201–18. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.Google Scholar
  6. Arrhenius, G. 2006a. Desert as fit: An axiomatic analysis. In The good, the right, life and death: Essays in honor of Fred Feldman, eds. R. Feldman, K. McDaniel, J. R. Raibley and M. J. Zimmerman. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing.Google Scholar
  7. Arrhenius, G. 2006b. The moral status of potential people. Department of Philosophy, Stockholm University (http://people.su.se/∼guarr/) (unpublished manuscript).
  8. Arrhenius, G., Ryberg, J., Tännsjö, T. 2006c. The Repugnant conclusion. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2006 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2006/entries/repugnant-conclusion/>.
  9. Arrhenius, G. 2007. Meritarian axiologies and distributive justice. In Hommage à Wlodek: Philosophical papers dedicated to Wlodek Rabinowicz, eds. T. Rønnow-Rasmussen, B. Petersson, J. Josefsson and D. Egonsson, 1–43 (www.fil.lu.se/hommageawlodek).Google Scholar
  10. Arrhenius, G. 2008. Life extension versus replacement. Journal of Applied Philosophy 25(3): 211–227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Arrhenius, G. 2009. Egalitarianism and population change. In Theories of intergenerational justice, eds. A. Gosseries and L. Meyer. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Bales, R. E. 1971. Act-utilitarianism: Account of right-making characteristic or decision-making procedure. American Philosophical Quarterly 8(3): 257–265.Google Scholar
  13. Brink, D. 1986. Utilitarian morality and the personal point of view. Journal of Philosophy 83(8): 417–438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Broome, J. 1991. Weighing goods: Equality, uncertainty, and time. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  15. Broome, J. 1992. Counting the costs of global warming. Cambridge: White Horse.Google Scholar
  16. Broome, J. 1999. Ethics out of economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Broome, J. 2004. Weighing Lives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Bykvist, K. 1998. Changing preferences: A study in preferentialism. Uppsala University (F.D. Diss.).Google Scholar
  19. Bykvist, K. 2007. The benefits of coming into existence. Philosophical Studies 135: 335–362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Carlson, E. 1995. Consequentialism reconsidered. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.Google Scholar
  21. Danielsson, S. 1974. Two papers on rationality and group preferences, Filosofiska Studier no. 21. Uppsala: Filosofiska föreningen och filosofiska institutionen.Google Scholar
  22. Feldman, F. 1997. Utilitarianism, hedonism, and desert: Essays in moral philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Feldman, F. 2006. Actual utility, the objection from impracticality, and the move to expected utility. Philosophical Studies 129: 49–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Glover, J. 1977. Causing death and saving lives. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  25. Heyd, D. 1988. Procreation and value: Can ethics deal with futurity problems. Philosophia (Israel) 18: 151–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Heyd, D. 1992. Genethics: Moral issues in the creation of people. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  27. Holtug, N. 1996. In defence of the slogan. In Preference and value: Preferentialism in ethics, ed. W. Rabinowicz, 64–89. Lund: Lund University (Department of Philosophy).Google Scholar
  28. Hope, T. 2003. Physicians’ duties and the non-identity problem, University of Oxford (unpublished manuscript).Google Scholar
  29. Kymlicka, W. 1990. Contemporary political philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  30. Meyer, L. 2003. Intergenerational Justice. Stanford encyclopaedia of philosophy.Google Scholar
  31. Moore, G. E. 1966. Principia ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Narveson, J. 1967. Utilitarianism and new generations.” Mind 76: 62–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Parfit, D. 1991. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  34. Rabinowicz, W. Broome and the intuition of neutrality. Philosophical Issues (forthcoming).Google Scholar
  35. Roberts, M. A. 1998. Child versus childmaker: Future persons and present duties in ethics and the law. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  36. Roberts, M. A. 2003a. Can it ever have been better never to have existed at all? Person-based consequentialism and a new repugnant conclusion. Journal of Applied Philosophy 20(2): 159–185.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Roberts, M. A. 2003b. Is the person-affecting intuition paradoxical? Theory and Decision 55: 1–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Roberts, M. A. 2007. The non-identity fallacy: Harm, probability and another look at Parfit’s depletion example. Utilitas 19(3): 267–311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Savulescu, J., Hemsley, M., Newson, A., Foddy, B. 2006. Behavioural genetics: Why eugenic selection is preferable to enhancement. Journal of Applied Philosophy 23(2): 157–171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Sidgwick, H. 1967. The methods of ethics (7th ed.). London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  41. Temkin, L. S. 1987. Intransitivity and the mere addition paradox. Philosophy and Public Affairs 16(2): 138–187.Google Scholar
  42. Temkin, L. S.1993a. Inequality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  43. Temkin, L. S.1993b. Harmful goods, harmless bads. In Value, welfare and morality, eds. R. G. Frey and C. W. Morris, 291–324. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Vallentyne, P. 1988. Gimmicky representations of moral theories. Metaphilosophy 19(34): 253–263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyStockholm University, Swedish Collegium for Advanced StudySweden

Personalised recommendations