Advertisement

Water is Not H2O

  • Michael Weisberg
Part of the Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science book series (BSPS, volume 242)

Conclusions

In this essay I have discussed an assumption of semantic externalist theories which I called the coordination principle. This is the idea that natural language kinds and scientific kinds line up or can be mapped onto one another one-to-one. A closer look at water shows that there is not this type of simple one-to-one match between chemical and ordinary language kinds. In fact, the use of kind terms in chemistry is often context sensitive and in cases where chemists want to ensure no ambiguity, they use a very complex and nuanced set of kind terms, none of which could be reasonably associated with the ordinary language kind term “water” alone. Since we cannot just turn to chemistry to find a single chemical kind that can be used to determine the extension of “water,” there is not any strict sense in which water is H2O, because exactly what water is depends on the context in which “water” is uttered.

Keywords

True Belief Natural Kind Ordinary Language Natural Kind Term Coordination Principle 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Devitt, M. and Sterelny, K. 1999. Language and Reality. Cambrdige, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  2. Dupré, J. 1993. The Disorder of Things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Johnson, M. 1997. Manifest kinds. Journal of Philosophy 94: 564–583.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Kripke, S.A. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambrdige, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Mellor, D. N. 1974. Natural kinds. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 28: 299–312.Google Scholar
  6. Needham, P. 2000. What is water? Analysis 60: 13–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Pauling, L. 1947. General Chemistry. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.Google Scholar
  8. Putnam, H. 1975. The meaning of ‘meaning’. In Mind, Language, and Reality. Collected Papers. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Sterelny, K. 1983. Natural kind terms. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64: 110–125.Google Scholar
  10. Stroll, A. 1998. Sketches of Landscapes: Philosophy by Example. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer 2006

Authors and Affiliations

  • Michael Weisberg
    • 1
  1. 1.University of PennsylvaniaUSA

Personalised recommendations